Catholic Teaching and the Kalaam Argument

While the Catholic Church holds that it is possible to prove the existence of God, it does not have teachings on specific versions of arguments for God’s existence and whether or not they work.

As a result, it does not have a teaching on the Kalaam cosmological argument, and Catholics are free to use it or not, depending on whether they think it works.

 

Catholic Liberty

Historically, major Catholic thinkers have taken different positions on the issue. St. Bonaventure (1221-1274) thought that the argument is successful, while his contemporary St. Thomas Aquinas (1225-1274) famously thought that it does not.

Both of these men have been declared doctors of the Church, meaning that they are among the best, most highly honored theologians.

A key premise of the Kalaam argument is that the universe has a beginning, which is certainly true. The question is how we can show this to a person who doesn’t already believe it.

Back in the 1200s, modern science had not yet been developed, and this premise had to be defended on purely philosophical grounds. On that score, I think St. Thomas Aquinas was right, and the philosophical arguments that have been proposed to show that the universe must have a finite history do not work.

However, in the 20th century the Big Bang was discovered, and current cosmology is consistent with the idea of the universe having a beginning. As a result, I think a properly qualified version of the Kalaam argument can be used, based on modern science.

 

Catholic Limits

While Catholic teaching allows great liberty when it comes to apologetic arguments, there are limits.

These limits are established by other teachings of the Church, and Catholic apologists need to be aware of them.

When it comes to the Kalaam argument, this is important because not all of the versions of it in circulation rely on assumptions consistent with Catholic teaching.

In particular, the foremost proponent of the Kalaam argument today—William Lane Craig—articulates it using concepts that clash with Catholic teaching, and Catholics who wish to use it need to be aware of this so that they can do the necessary filtering.

Specifically: Craig (who is not Catholic) holds that God is not eternal in the sense that the Church understands.

He does hold that God has always existed and that God would exist if the world (including time) had never come into being. However, he holds that due to the creation of the world, God exists inside of time rather than outside of it.

 

Eternity and Catholic Teaching

The classic definition of eternity was given by the Christian philosopher Boethius (c. 480-c. 525). He defined eternity this way:

Eternity, then, is the complete, simultaneous, and perfect possession of everlasting [Latin, interminabilis = “interminable,” “unending”] life; this will be clear from a comparison with creatures that exist in time (The Consolation of Philosophy, 5:6, emphasis added).

Eternity, then, is “the complete, simultaneous, and perfect possession of unending life.” It is something possessed by God and not possessed by creatures that exist in time. We may be everlasting—and we will be, for God will give us endless life—but God is fundamentally outside of time.

Boethius’s definition became standard in Catholic thought, and it was the definition in use when in 1215 the Fourth Lateran Council taught:

Firmly we believe and we confess simply that the true God is one alone, eternal, immense, and unchangeable, incomprehensible, omnipotent, and ineffable (DS 800).

The same definition was standard when in 1870 the First Vatican Council taught:

The Holy, Catholic, Apostolic and Roman Church believes and acknowledges that there is one true and living God, creator and lord of heaven and earth, almighty, eternal, immeasurable, incomprehensible, infinite in will, understanding and every perfection (Dei Filius, 1:1; DS 3001).

St. John Paul II made the implications of this more explicit when he taught:

These facts of revelation also express the rational conviction to which one comes when one considers that God is the subsisting Being, and therefore necessary, and therefore eternal.

Because he cannot not be, he cannot have beginning or end nor a succession of moments in the only and infinite act of his existence.

Right reason and revelation wonderfully converge on this point.

Being God, absolute fullness of being, (ipsum Esse subsistens), his eternity “inscribed in the terminology of being” must be understood as the “indivisible, perfect, and simultaneous possession of an unending life,” and therefore as the attribute of being absolutely “beyond time” (General Audience, Sept. 4, 1985).

Catholic teaching thus holds that God is eternal in the sense of being “absolutely beyond time” and that for him there is no “succession of moments in the only and infinite act of his existence.”

Everything God knows, he knows at once, and everything God does, he does at once. He doesn’t learn something, wait a little while, and then learn something new. Neither does he do something, wait a little while, and then do something new. His knowledge and his actions are all timeless and simultaneous.

 

Implications for Time

The fact that God is outside of time has implications for how we view time itself. Two key concepts we need to understand are called eternalism and presentism.

    • Eternalism is the view that the past, present, and future are all real from the ultimate perspective—that is, the perspective of God in eternity.
    • Presentism can be understood different ways, but here we will be concerned with what can be called “strict presentism,” which means that from the ultimate perspective, only the present is real. The past and the future do not exist at all.

If God is eternal, it is very difficult to see how presentism can be true. In fact, I would say that the ideas of divine eternity and strict presentism are mutually exclusive.

The reason is that, as John Paul II stated, there is no “succession of moments” for God. The “eternal now” in which God dwells constitutes “the only and infinite act of his existence.”

This means that everything that God does, he does simultaneously, and that includes creating all the different moments in time that we inhabit.

Thus, in his timeless, eternal now, God is simultaneously creating the stretch of time that we call 2021 . . . and the stretch of time we call 2022 . . . and 2023 . . . and so on.

But if God creates something, it is real from his perspective, and so 2021 is just as real to God as 2022 and 2023 and every other year in the history of the universe.

For God, our past, present, and future are equally real, and that implies eternalism.

 

Catholic Presentism?

There are Catholic thinkers who refer to themselves as presentists, but I am not aware of any who hold the strict presentism.

The response I’ve received when pointing out the fact that God must be eternally and simultaneously creating all the moments in history has been to the effect of:

Yes, of course, from God’s perspective, all of history must be real.

What I want to emphasize by speaking of presentism is that from our perspective in time the past is no longer real, and the future is not yet real. The passage of time is not an illusion.

And I agree with that. The passage of time is not an illusion. We are clearly moving through time, and if you take time as your frame of reference rather than eternity, the past and the future aren’t real, but the present is.

If these points are agreed to, whether one wants to call one’s position eternalism (viewing things from God’s eternal frame of reference) or presentism (viewing them from our temporal frame of reference) may be more a matter of semantics than substance.

But this Catholic presentism is not the same as the strict presentism described above, because that view holds that the past and the future are not just unreal from our perspective, but from God’s too. They simply don’t exist at all.

The eternalist (or Catholic presentist position we’ve described) has implications for the Kalaam argument. In particular, it has implications for two of the premises in Craig’s key arguments.

 

Actual Infinities

One of Craig’s key arguments goes like this:

1) An actually infinite number of things cannot exist.

2) A beginningless series of events in time entails an actually infinite number of things.

3) Therefore, a beginningless series of events in time cannot exist.

Here the problematic premise is the first.

The Christian faith holds that God will give us endless life in the future. We will not pass out of existence either at our death or at any point thereafter.

Viewed from within time, this endless existence is a potential infinite—meaning that we will experience an unlimited number of days, but those days don’t all exist at the same time.

However, from God’s perspective outside of time, they do all exist, because God is simultaneously creating each one of them, making them real from his perspective.

As a result, there are an actually infinite number of days from God’s perspective, and so actual infinities can exist in that frame of reference.

This means that the first premise of the argument is false from this perspective, and that fact undermines its conclusion.

On eternalism, the Christian faith implies that an actual infinity of future days does exist, and that implies that an actual infinity of past days can exist.

Speaking from our perspective inside time, this past infinity of days wouldn’t all exist at once—meaning they’re not an actual infinity from our perspective any more than the infinity of future days ahead of us is.

In fact, this corresponds to the view of Aristotle (who pioneered the concept of non-actual infinities). He held that the world had existed endlessly into the past, but this wasn’t a problem because all those days didn’t exist at the same time, making them a non-actual infinity.

 

Forming an Infinite by Successive Addition

Craig’s other key argument goes like this:

1) The series of events in time is a collection formed by adding one member after another.

2) A collection formed by adding one member after another cannot be actually infinite.

3) Therefore, the series of events in time cannot be actually infinite.

Here, again, the problematic premise is the first.

(Actually, the second premise also either involves a fallacy or is just false, but we’ll focus on the first one here.)

While it may be true that, from a perspective inside time, events grow in number by adding one new event after another, this isn’t true from God’s perspective.

On Christian eternalism, God exists in a single, timeless moment and does all of his creating activity simultaneously.

He thus is not creating the different years of history in a one-after-the-other fashion. He creates all of them at once, including the infinite years of life ahead of us. From the eternal perspective, Flash! An infinity of future years exists.

And so, the first premise would be false.

 

Craig’s Position

Craig appears sensitive to these considerations, and thus he is a strong advocate of strict presentism—to the point that he is willing to say that, since the creation of time, God has a temporal mode of existence.

I think this is something he would have to do, because if the present is the only thing that exist, it would force changes in God’s knowledge.

For example, at one moment, God would know “It is currently 12:00 p.m.,” but then a minute later he would know “It is currently 12:01 p.m.” This is because God knows whatever is true, and if only the present is real then what is true changes from moment to moment.

God’s knowledge thus would have to change to keep up with changing reality, and so God would be changeable rather than changeless, and thus subject to time.

The alternative would be to say that, from his perspective outside of time, God knows things like “At point X in time, it is 12:00 p.m. and at point Y in time, it is 12:01 p.m.” This allows God to know both facts about time simultaneously, in a changeless manner that preserves his eternity.

These two ways of looking at things are often framed in philosophical discussions in terms of the “A-theory of time” and the “B-theory of time.” Without getting into the weeds, the A-theory is associated with (but not the same thing as) presentism, while the B-theory is associated with eternalism.

Also important to the discussion is the distinction between “tensed propositions,” which change their truth value over time (e.g., “It is now 12:00 p.m.”) and “tenseless propositions,” which do not (e.g., “At point X in time, it is 12:00 p.m.”).

Tensed propositions are important for the A-theory (also called the “tensed theory of time”) and presentism, while a tenseless understanding is important for the B-theory (or “tenseless theory of time”) and eternalism.

If you read Craig’s works and watch his presentations, he frequently appeals to tensed propositions, the A-theory, and presentism in order to defend his philosophical arguments for the universe having a beginning.

They are key to his presentation. In fact, he has said that he thinks that the importance of the tensed theory of time for the Kalaam argument cannot be overstated.

He’s also acknowledged that if the B-theory of time or an atemporal understanding is true, it would damage to his presentations. He would abandon the argument from successive addition (as we noted should be done, above) and that he would have to reformulate defenses of other aspects of the argument, though the scientific evidence points to the universe having a beginning.

 

Implications for Catholic Apologists

In light of what we’ve seen, Catholic apologists need to be aware that they cannot simply take Craig’s presentations of the Kalaam argument and make them their own, repeating them as if they were all consistent with Catholic teaching.

Instead, they need to use critical thinking to sort the elements that are from the elements that aren’t.

In particular, they need to be aware that the Church disagrees with Craig when it comes to God having a temporal mode of existence and having knowledge that changes (as with tensed propositions and the A-theory of time).

For a Catholic, his arguments dealing with the A-theory and tensed propositions need serious revision or abandonment.

Similarly, if God creates all the moments of time simultaneously from the perspective of his eternal now, it has implications for the past and the future, as well as the present, being real.

This undermines the premises of the two key philosophical arguments Craig makes for a finite history (i.e., that actual infinities cannot exist and that the events in time are formed by successive addition from God’s perspective).

While Catholic teaching has serious implications for the kind of arguments that can be used in support of the overall Kalaam argument, and while careful discernment is needed on this point, I agree that the argument is still sound.

I disagree with Craig that the philosophical arguments for the universe having a beginning work, but I agree with him that the scientific evidence does point in this direction, and so I ultimately agree with him that a reformulated version of the argument can be used.

Can an Actual Infinity Exist?

We know that God created the universe a finite amount of time ago, but defenders of the Kalaam cosmological argument say that God had to do it this way. He had no other choice.

William Lane Craig has proposed the following argument to support this claim:

1) An actually infinite number of things cannot exist.

2) A beginningless series of events in time entails an actually infinite number of things.

3) Therefore, a beginningless series of events in time cannot exist.

Depending on your view of time, there are potential problems with the second premise—as I’ve written elsewhere.

However, here I’d like to consider the first premise.

Is it true that an actually infinite number of things can’t exist?

 

What’s an “Actual” Infinite?

We need to be aware of the difference between what philosophers and mathematicians call “potential” infinities and “actual” infinities.

    • Something is potentially infinite if it goes on endlessly, but there is no frame of reference in which all of its elements exist.
    • Something is actually infinite if it goes on endlessly and there is a frame of reference in which all its elements exist.

For example, suppose that you have a machine that makes cubes. Today it makes a cube, tomorrow it makes a cube, and it keeps on like that endlessly. No matter how many days you go into the future, there will still be a finite (limited) number of cubes.

From within the perspective of time, there is no day where the “infinity-eth” cube pops out of the machine, because “infinity” is not a number on the number line. There is no “number just before infinity,” and so you can’t count to infinity.

Yet the series of cubes that the machine will make is endless, which is what “infinite” means—unlimited or unending (Latin, in- “not” + finis = “limit, end”).

So, while the number of cubes you have grows toward infinity, it never gets there. That’s why the cubes would be said to be potentially infinite rather than actually infinite—because they don’t all exist at the same time.

But suppose you didn’t have a cube-making machine. Suppose instead that God decided to create an infinite number of cubes all at once. Bam! It’s done. All in a flash.

In this case, you would have an infinite number of cubes—that all exist at once—and so that would be an actually infinite set of cubes.

The key point to remember is that both potential infinites and actual infinites involve limitless numbers of things. The difference is that in a potential infinity these elements don’t all exist at once, while in an actual infinity, they do.

 

Can Actual Infinities Exist?

While many authors assert that actual infinities can’t exist, we should test this. Can we think of anything actually infinite?

How about numbers?

We often represent the set of natural numbers like this: {0, 1, 2, 3 . . . }. The reason we put the ellipsis (the three dots) at the end is to say that this series of numbers goes on forever in the same way it began, with one number after another, with no end to them.

That’s an infinite set!

And all those numbers already exist. It’s not like there’s a mathematician somewhere inventing new numbers in his workshop.

We may make up names for new numbers—like the number googol, which is 10-to-the-power-of-100, or googolplex, which is 10-to-the-power-of-googol—but we didn’t create these numbers. We only named them.

Even before they were thought of or named, it would remain true that googol multiplied by 2 is 2 googol, that googol minus google is 0, and that googol divided by google is 1.

So, it appears that an infinite quantity of natural numbers exists, whether we’ve thought of or named them or not.

Since the set of numbers does not grow with time—only our knowledge of them does—the set of natural numbers is an actually infinite set, as mathematicians commonly acknowledge.

 

The Truth of the Matter

Numbers are not the only actual infinity we can think of. There also are truths (facts), as we can easily see:

    • It is true that 1 + 1 = 2.
    • It is true that 2 + 1 = 3.
    • It is true that 3 + 1 = 4.
    • And so on.

So, not only does an actually infinite quantity of numbers exist, an actually infinite quantity of truths also does.

How might a defender of the Kalaam argument respond to this?

 

The Nature of Numbers and Truths

It’s easy to point out that there is a difference between numbers and truths and the kind of objects we see in the world around us.

For example, if I have two cubes that I’m holding in my hands, I’m physically touching them. But I don’t seem to be touching the number 2. Numbers aren’t physical objects you can see, hear, or touch.

Neither are truths. It may be a truth that Abraham Lincoln died in 1865, but I can’t hold this truth in my hands like an apple or put a ruler beside it and measure how long it is.

Things like numbers and truths seem to be in a different category than things like cubes and apples. Things in the first category are often called abstract objects, while those in the latter are often called concrete objects. We also might call them physical objects.

The sciences have given us a lot of information about how physical objects work, but we can’t use science to investigate abstract ones. They lie in the realm of philosophy, and among philosophers there are different views about their nature.

Some philosophers (known as anti-realists) deny that abstract objects are real and propose other ways of understanding them. Other philosophers (known as realists) hold that they do exist, but again there are different understandings (e.g., do abstract objects exist in an abstract realm of some kind? do they only exist in physical objects? are they based in the mind of God?).

 

Options for the Kalaam Defender

A Kalaam defender could adopt an anti-realist position and say that things like numbers and truths simply do not exist, which would mean that there aren’t actual infinities of these—because numbers and truths don’t exist in the first place!

But this seems hard for many to imagine, including various supporters of the Kalaam argument.

There is another option, which is to draw a line between the two classes of objects and say something like, “Look, whether or not actual infinities of abstract objects exist (maybe they do; maybe they don’t), that’s not what I’m talking about. When I say that actual infinities can’t exist, I mean that they can’t exist concretely, in the physical world.”

A person taking this position could acknowledge that actual infinities of abstract objects can exist. What he disputes is that actual infinities of concrete, physical ones can.

 

Why Not?

The question would be: Why not? Why can’t actual infinities of physical objects be real?

This question is particularly acute from a Christian perspective, since the Christian faith holds that God exists and that he is omnipotent, which means that he can create anything that does not involve a logical contradiction.

So, let’s do a thought experiment:

Imagine a cubic foot of empty space that has a single hydrogen atom in it. If we can imagine that, so can God.

Now imagine a second cubic foot of empty space sitting right next to it, also with a hydrogen atom in it. God can imagine that, too.

Now put a third cubic foot of space next to that, also with a hydrogen atom, so that we have a row of three.

Then imagine a fourth, a fifth, a sixth, and so on. God can imagine each of these as the line of cubic feet extends off into the distance.

In fact—due to his omniscience—God can imagine any number of such units. Unless there is a logical contradiction involved, God could imagine a cubic foot of space with a hydrogen atom for every natural number.

And so, God can imagine an actually infinite volume of space, with a single hydrogen atom in each cubic foot.

Either this scenario involves a logical contradiction or it doesn’t. If it doesn’t, then God can imagine it, since God can do anything logically possible.

And it does not appear to involve a contradiction. As even many defenders of the Kalaam argument admit, the mathematics of infinity are consistent and do not contain logical contradictions.

This situation isn’t like saying, “Suppose God imagines a four-sided triangle.” Not even God can visualize that, because “four-sided triangle” is a contradiction in terms.

“Four-sided” and “triangular” mean different and contradictory things. This expression is just word salad—not something that is actually meaningful.

But our volume of space isn’t like that. Even our puny minds can imagine a row of cubic feet with hydrogen atoms in them. God’s mind is infinite, and so he can imagine the line of cubic feet extending on endlessly—and there doesn’t seem to be a logical contradiction involved in him doing that.

If there’s not, then we’re ready to add a new element to our thought experiment.

 

“Let There Be Space!”

Because of his omnipotence, God can do anything that doesn’t involve a logical contradiction. So, if God can imagine something, he can also create it.

As a result, if the idea of an infinite row of cubic feet of space—each with a hydrogen atom—doesn’t involve a logical contradiction, then God can make it real.

God thus could create an infinite number of hydrogen atoms and an infinite volume of space to contain them.

If God chooses, actual infinities of physical things could exist!

The only way to avoid this would be to say that, even though the idea of finite space with finite atoms is logically coherent, a contradiction in terms is generated if we extend this to infinity.

In that case, God couldn’t imagine or create this any more than he could a four-sided triangle.

But in that case, I want to know: What’s the contradiction?

As we’ve discussed, a Christian who understands God’s omnipotence should affirm that God can make something unless it is shown to involve a logical contradiction.

The Kalaam defender thus needs to name the contradiction: Which are the specific terms that contradict?

And it won’t do to change the scenario and pose some other one where a new logically contradictory entity is subtly introduced. That happens all too often.

Changing the scenario is what you do when you can’t deal with the current one.

Neither is it sufficient to say, “Hey, infinities have weird properties.” Yes, they do. That doesn’t mean they’re beyond the reach of God’s omnipotence.

So please, deal with the thought experiment I’ve described, flesh out its terms in detail, and name which terms contradict each other—just like how I pointed out that “four-sided” and “triangular” contradict.

Either that or be prepared to acknowledge that God has the power to create actual infinities of physical objects.

 

Grim Reapers, Paradoxes, and Infinite History

We know from Scripture that God created the world a finite amount of time ago, but was that the only option he had? Could God have created a world with an infinite history?

Defenders of the Kalaam cosmological argument claim that he couldn’t have done so.

To show that, they would need to demonstrate that the idea of an infinite history involves a logical contradiction.

Some recent attempts to do this involve paradoxes that have been proposed by different authors.

Let’s look at a couple and see what we can learn.

 

The (Squished) Grim Reaper Paradox

The core of what has become known as the Grim Reaper paradox was proposed by Jose Bernardete, and the argument has taken different forms.

Here I’ll present a version that is close to the original. I’ll refer to it as the “squished” version for reasons that will become obvious.

Suppose that a guy named Fred is alive at 12:00 noon.

However, there are an infinite number of grim reapers waiting to kill him. For the sake of convenience, we will give the reapers names based on the negative numbers, with the last reaper being Reaper 0.

If Fred is still alive at 1 p.m., Reaper 0 will encounter him and kill him. However, before that, Reaper -1 will encounter Fred at 12:30 p.m. and kill him. Even before that, Reaper -2 will encounter Fred at 12:15 p.m. and kill him. But Reaper -3 will encounter him at 12:07:30 p.m., and so on, with each reaper set to encounter (and kill) Fred in half the remaining distance back to noon.

Which reaper will kill Fred?

The way the situation has been set up, we have a paradox. Reaper 0 should not kill Fred, because Fred should already have been killed by Reaper -1. But this reaper shouldn’t kill him either, because he should have been killed by Reaper -2. And Reaper -3 should have killed him before that, and so on.

It thus looks like Fred can’t possibly survive past 12:00 noon, but it’s impossible to name which reaper kills him. Paradox.

I called the above version “squished” because it squishes the infinite series of grim reapers into a single hour. But we don’t have to do it that way. We’ll see another version later.

 

The Problem with the Paradox

The resolution of this paradox is fairly straightforward. It has envisioned a situation where Fred begins alive and then will be killed by the first grim reaper he encounters.

The problem is that—if the series of grim reapers is infinite—then it must have no beginning.

To suppose that an infinite series of whole numbers has both a first and last member involves what I’ve called the First-and-Last Fallacy.

    • Infinite series can have no beginning ( . . . -3, -2, -1, 0)
    • They can have no end (0, 1, 2, 3 . . .)
    • Or they can lack both a beginning and an end ( . . . -3, -2, -1, 0, 1, 2, 3 . . . )

But if a series has both a beginning and an end, then it’s finite.

The series of reapers set to kill Fred has an end—Reaper 0—but if that’s the case, it cannot have a beginning.

This means that there is no first grim reaper that Fred encounters, just as there is no “first negative number.”

The idea of a first negative number involves a logical contradiction, and therefore the (Squished) Grim Reaper paradox is proposing a situation that cannot exist.

 

The (Spread-Out) Grim Reaper Paradox

To make the Grim Reaper Paradox more relevant to the Kalaam argument, some have proposed a new version that spreads out the grim reapers over an infinite history rather than squishing them into a single hour.

We can put the spread-out version like this:

Suppose that Fred has always been alive, all the way through an infinite past.

Suppose that there is an infinite series of grim reapers set to kill Fred, and they are set to kill him in sequence on New Year’s Day.

On New Year’s Day this year, Reaper 0 is set to kill him if he is still alive. But on New Year’s Day last year, Reaper -1 was set to kill him, and Reaper -2 the year before that, and so on.

Which reaper kills Fred?

Exactly the same paradox results. Each reaper should not be able to kill Fred because a previous reaper should already have done the dirty work.

But the problem is the same: The situation is set up so that the only reaper that could kill Fred is the first one in a beginningless series, and a beginningless series has no first element.

The spread-out version of the paradox thus has the same flaw that the original did: It proposes an entity that involves a logical contradiction and so can’t exist.

 

Application to the Kalaam Argument

Kalaam defenders use paradoxes like this in an attempt to undermine the idea of an infinite history.

For example, on the rhetorical level, the strategy can work like this:

    • They encourage their audience to imagine a set of circumstances that could exist and that don’t involve a logical contradiction (e.g., Fred exists, a grim reaper is scheduled to kill him at some time).
    • They multiply the circumstance extending finitely into the past (suppose there are some other grim reapers who were also set to kill him previously).
    • They extend this infinitely into the past, generating a contradiction.
    • They point out this contradiction.
    • Finally, they assert that, since the infinite extension into the past caused the contradiction, we must reject the idea of an infinite past.

This reasoning is mistaken, because it isn’t the infinite history that’s the problem. It’s the fact that you’ve proposed a first element in a beginningless series.

Consider the following scenario:

    • Suppose that some guy named Fred exists.
    • Suppose that he existed last year.
    • And the year before that.
    • And that he’s always existed, with no beginning.

That involves an infinite history, but it doesn’t have a contradiction in it—because it does not propose a first element in a beginningless series.

It’s only when you introduce the latter that a contradiction occurs. So, it isn’t the infinite history that’s the problem but the impossible first element. Grim Reaper-like paradoxes thus are disguised forms of the First-and-Last Fallacy.

 

World Without End

Another way of seeing why the strategy used by Kalaam defenders is problematic is by flipping the arrow of time and considering a mirror image of the paradox that deals with the future:

Suppose that Fred is alive today and will remain alive as long as a grim reaper doesn’t kill him.

Suppose that there is an infinite series of grim reapers to kill him in the future and who we will name using the positive numbers, beginning with 0. Reaper 0 encounters Fred today, Reaper 1 encounters him tomorrow, Reaper 2 the day after, and so on.

But the reapers have agreed that the honor of killing Fred will go to the reaper with the highest number.

Which reaper kills Fred?

The way this scenario has been set up, the only reaper that can kill Fred is the last reaper.

But there can be no last reaper in a series that has no end, just as there can be no first reaper in a series that has no beginning.

The Future Reaper Paradox proposes the same kind of logically contradictory entity that the original paradoxes did.

And the problem is not the fact that the future is infinite in the scenario. The infinite future itself does not involve a contradiction, because it does not propose there being a last element in the series of days stretching into the future.

Indeed! From a Christian point of view, an infinite future is exactly what awaits us. The Christian faith teaches that God will give us endless life and there will be no day on which we pass out of existence. As a result, an orthodox Christian is committed to the idea of an infinite future.

It’s not the endlessness of the future that’s a problem in the above scenario, but the idea of that future containing a logically contradictory entity like the last member of an endless series of reapers.

In the same way, the idea of an infinite past is not a logical contradiction but the idea of a first reaper in a beginningless series.

 

The Underlying Assumptions

The paradoxes recently proposed in support of the Kalaam argument (and there are many) share a common set of assumptions:

    1. Suppose some past scenario (P) that involves a first member.
    2. Suppose some past scenario (P’) that does not have a first member.
    3. Suppose that P and P’ are the same scenario.

By contrast, corresponding future-oriented paradoxes have these assumptions:

    1. Suppose some future scenario (F) that involves a last member.
    2. Suppose some future scenario (F’) that does not have a last member.
    3. Suppose that F and F’ are the same scenario.

The way the paradoxes are fleshed out and expressed varies, and this can disguise the fact, but they all share the same set of assumptions.

As a result, they set up logical contradictions, but this does not tell us which of the premises must be rejected to diffuse the contradiction.

This is true of any such paradox. Consider the following geometrical one:

    1. Suppose there is some closed geometrical shape (S) that has three sides.
    2. Suppose that there is some closed geometrical shape (S’) that has four sides.
    3. Suppose that S and S’ are the same shape.

This scenario sets up the idea of a four-sided triangle, which is logically impossible. But in resolving the paradox, we don’t have to reject any particular premise.

We could reject the idea that S (the three-sided shape) exists; we could reject the idea that (S’) the four-sided shape exists; or we could reject the idea that S and S’ are the same and then conclude that there must be two shapes. Each of these is a legitimate option.

As a result, when considering past- or future-oriented paradoxes, we don’t have to reject the idea of an infinite past or an infinite future, because neither of these concepts generates a logical contradiction on its own.

It is only when we introduce a logically contradictory entity into these scenarios—like the first member of a beginningless series or the last member in an endless series—that a paradox results.

Those are the entities that need to be rejected, and the recently proposed paradoxes do not disprove either the idea of an infinite past or an infinite future.

Omnipotence and Infinite History

God chose to create the world a finite amount of time ago, but could he have chosen otherwise?

According to defenders of the Kalaam cosmological argument, the answer is no. He could not have done so, and the world must have a finite history. Even God could not create an infinite one.

Others, such as St. Thomas Aquinas, disagree and hold that God could have done this if he chose.

How can we navigate this issue?

The Burden of Proof

People who disagree sometimes get into squabbles about who has the burden of proof—that is, who needs to provide proof of their position.

While special rules may apply in a courtroom or in a formal debate, the answer for ordinary purposes is clear. It can be stated in the form of a simple and powerful rule.

The Iron Rule of the Burden of Proof: Whoever wants someone to change his mind has the burden of proof.

If I want you to change your mind, I need to give you evidence (arguments, proof) why you should do so. If you want me to change my mind, you need to.

Much needless squabbling would be avoided if people kept this rule in mind.

Applying this to our question:

    • If a Kalaam proponent wants to convince someone that God couldn’t create a world with an infinite history, he needs to provide evidence why he couldn’t.
    • If a Kalaam skeptic wants to convince someone that God could create a world with an infinite history, he needs to provide evidence why he could.
    • If they both want to convince each other, they both need to do this.

I’m a Kalaam skeptic, so let me give you the evidence that causes me to take this position.

“With God All Things Are Possible”

The Christian faith holds that God is all-powerful, or omnipotent. Jesus himself tells us, “With God all things are possible” (Matt. 19:26).

Thus, the default answer for any question that takes the form “Could God create X?” is “Yes.”

If you want to move off that default answer, you’ll need to show something very specific. This is because, over the centuries, theologians have discerned that there is only one type of situation that falls outside the scope of God’s omnipotence: logical contradictions.

No, God can’t make married bachelors, square circles, or four-sided triangles. Each of these involves a contradiction in terms, or what philosophers call a logical contradiction.

They don’t represent possible entities. They’re just word salad. They may at first sound like something that could exist, but as soon as you think about the meaning of the words involved, you realize that they can’t.

So, while “with God all things are possible,” these aren’t things. “Square circle” and “four-sided triangle” are just nonsense phrases.

“Infinite History”?

In light of this principle, if I ask myself, “Could God create a world with an infinite history?” my default answer will be “Yes”—just as it would be on any other subject.

For me to move off that default answer, I’d need to be shown that the concept of a world with an infinite history involves a logical contradiction.

The same should be true of every Christian who understands God’s omnipotence.

Thus far, despite extensive research, I have not been able to find a logical contradiction. And, as a result, I am of the opinion that one does not exist.

Consider Craig

Consider the arguments proposed by William Lane Craig, the best-known defender of the Kalaam argument.

He has spent an enormous amount of time thinking, writing, and defending it. If anyone should have found a logical contradiction in the concept, it should be him!

Yet, in his books, debates, speeches, and videos, I haven’t found him asserting that the concept of an infinite history involves a logical contradiction. If anything, he seems to carefully avoid saying that.

He concedes that the mathematics of infinity are logically consistent—that they don’t involve a logical contradiction—so, it isn’t that the concept of infinity is problematic.

Instead, he asserts that actual infinities can’t exist in the real world, so the real world’s history can’t be infinite.

But what is it about the concept of “infinity” and the concept of “history” that prevents the two from being brought together? Both concepts are fine on their own. Where’s the logical contradiction?

Craig never seems to say. Instead, I find him saying two things:

    1. An actual infinity that exists in the real world would be “metaphysically impossible.”
    2. If an actual infinity existed in the real world, the results would be “absurd.”

“Metaphysically Impossible”

Sometimes Craig states that it would be metaphysically impossible for the world to have an infinite history. What does this mean?

Philosophers and theologians speak about different types of possibility. For example:

    • Something is logically possible if it does not involve a contradiction in terms.
    • Something is metaphysically possible if it could happen in reality, even if the world operated under very different physical laws.
    • Something is physically possible if it could happen in our world, given the way its physical laws operate (e.g., the speed of light, conservation of mass and energy).
    • Something is practically possible if we could realistically do it, given our limitations (e.g., how much time we have, how big our budget is).

Philosophers often say that metaphysical possibility is notoriously hard to define, and from a secular perspective, this might be true.

However, for a Christian who understands God’s omnipotence, it shouldn’t be.

    1. God can do anything that doesn’t involve a logical contradiction.
    2. Therefore, God can make any world that doesn’t involve a logical contradiction.
    3. Therefore, anything that is logically possible is metaphysically possible.

For the Christian, logical possibility and metaphysical possibility are really two ways of describing the same thing.

If—on the logical level—there’s a contradiction in terms, then that means—on the metaphysical level—that there is a contradiction in the nature of the things those terms describe.

Let’s suppose that you want to draw a four-sided triangle. On the logical level, there is a contradiction between four-sidedness and being a triangle, and on the metaphysical level, triangular objects are such that they cannot have four sides.

As a result, the question of metaphysical impossibility collapses into the question of logical possibility.

Consequently, logical impossibility is what Craig needs to show if he wants to deny that God can’t make a world with an infinite history.

To say that such a thing would be metaphysically impossible is, for the Christian who understands God’s omnipotence, just another way of saying that it involves a logical contradiction.

“Absurd”

What about Craig’s other claim—that an actual infinity in the real world would result in “absurd” situations?

Craig makes this charge in connection with a famous thought experiment known as Hilbert’s Hotel, which was proposed by the mathematician David Hilbert.

It involves a hotel that has an infinite number of rooms, and—because of the strange properties that infinity has—you can imagine some very strange things happening at the hotel. (You can read about them at the link.)

There are various ways of responding. Hilbert’s Hotel actually isn’t as strange as it sounds once you think about what “infinite” means. Also, it’s just a physicalization of the concept of infinity, with one room for every natural number. So, if the idea of an infinite set of natural numbers doesn’t involve a logical contradiction, neither should a physical representation of it.

However, to keep our discussion concise, I want to focus on this: “Absurd” does not mean “logically contradictory.”

Something is absurd if it strikes us as surprising, counter-intuitive, and contrary to our expectations—prompting us to have an impulse to reject the idea out of hand.

But it turns out that the world contains many things that strike us as absurd and yet turn out to be true. This is the case regardless of one’s persuasions. One can be Christian, Jewish, Muslim, Atheist, or anything else, and the world still contains a lot of strange, “absurd” things.

Lots of people—in history and today—have found each of the following claims absurd:

    • An infinitely loving God would allow innocent people and animals to suffer.
    • God would send someone to hell.
    • God became man.
    • God died on a cross.
    • There is one God, who is a Trinity of Persons.
    • Transubstantiation occurs.
    • God created the world out of nothing.
    • The earth is a sphere.
    • The sun does not orbit the earth.
    • Man can build machines that will enable him to fly.
    • Man can go to the moon.
    • Modern life forms are the product of a process of evolution stretching back billions of years.
    • There was a beginning to time.
    • Space and time are not absolutes but can be warped by gravity.
    • When you move faster, time slows down.
    • Heavier objects do not fall appreciably faster than lighter ones.
    • Atoms exist.
    • In the Monty Hall Problem, the best strategy is to switch your bet after the first door is opened.

Yet each of these is true. So, from a Christian perspective, we can say that God has created a world where a lot of “absurd” things in it.

Consequently, if we want our beliefs to be accurate, we need to be willing to consider ideas that strike us as absurd and not simply dismiss them on this basis.

The fact that something seems absurd is not a reliable guide to what God can do, and so it’s not enough to allow us to say, “God can’t do that.”

If we want to say that God can’t make a world with an infinite history, we need more than gesturing at a situation and saying it’s absurd.

We need to know what logical contradiction it involves. We need to be able to name the terms that produce a logical contradiction.

So far, Craig hasn’t identified one, but that’s what we need to see.

Until he or someone else can show that the idea of infinite history involves a contradiction in terms (and name the terms that conflict!), any Christian who understands God’s omnipotence should remain with the default position that this would be within God’s power.

Using the Kalaam Argument Correctly

In recent years, one of the most popular arguments for the existence of God has been the Kalaam cosmological argument.

Ultimately, I think this argument is successful, but many of the ways it has been employed are unsuccessful.

It is an argument that needs to be used carefully—with the proper qualifiers.

 

Stating the Argument

We can state the Kalaam argument like this:

1) Everything that has a beginning has a cause.

2) The universe has a beginning.

3) Therefore, the universe has a cause (which would be God).

Is this argument valid? Is it sound?

Valid arguments are ones that use a correct logical form—regardless of whether their premises are true. The Kalaam argument falls into this category, which is not disputed by its critics.

If a valid argument has true premises, then its conclusion also will be true. Valid arguments that have true premises are called sound arguments, and I agree that the argument’s premises are true:

1) It is true that whatever has a beginning has a cause.

2) And it is true that the universe has a beginning (approximately 13.8 billion years ago, according to Big Bang cosmology).

Since the Kalaam argument is valid and has true premises, it is a sound argument.

 

Using the Argument Apologetically

The Kalaam argument is sound from the perspective of logic, but how useful is it from the perspective of apologetics? There are many arguments that are sound, but sometimes they are not very useful in practice.

For example, in their famous book Principia Mathematica, Bertrand Russell and Alfred North Whitehead spend the first 360 pages of the book covering basic principles that build up to them rigorously proving that 1 + 1 = 2.

While their book is of interest to mathematicians, and their proof extremely well thought-out, it is so complex that it is not of practical use for a popular audience. For ordinary people, there are much simpler ways to prove that 1 + 1 = 2. (If needed, just put one apple on a table, put another one next to it, and count the apples both individually and together.)

Complexity is not the only thing that can limit an argument’s usefulness. Another is the willingness of people to grant the truth of its premises. Here is where some of the limitations of the Kalaam argument appear. While it is very simple to state and understand, defending the premises is more involved.

 

The First Premise

The first premise—that everything that has a beginning has a cause—is intuitive and is accepted by most people.

Some object to this premise on philosophical grounds or on scientific ones, such as by pointing to the randomness of quantum physics.

Both the philosophical and the scientific arguments can get technical quickly, but a skilled apologist—at least one who is actually familiar with quantum mechanics (!)—would still be able to navigate such objections without getting too far over the heads of a popular audience.

This—plus the fact that a popular audience’s sympathies will be with the first premise—mean that the argument retains its usefulness with a general audience.

 

The Second Premise

The second premise—that the universe had a beginning—is also widely accepted today, due in large part to Big Bang cosmology. A popular audience will thus be generally sympathetic to the second premise.

That’s apologetically useful, but we need to look more closely at how the second premise can be supported when challenged.

Since “The Bible says the universe has a beginning” will not be convincing to those who are not already believers, there are two approaches to doing this—the scientific and the philosophical.

 

The Scientific Approach

For an apologist, the approach here is straight forward: For a popular level audience, simply present a popular-level account of the evidence that has led cosmologists to conclude that the Big Bang occurred.

On this front, the principal danger for the apologist is overselling the evidence in one of several ways.

First, many apologists do not keep up with developments in cosmology, and they may be relying on an outdated account of the Big Bang.

For example, about 40 years ago, it was common to hear cosmologists speak of the Big Bang as an event that involved a singularity—where all matter was compressed into a point of infinite density and when space and time suddenly sprang into existence.

That view is no longer standard in cosmology, and today no apologist should be speaking as if this is what the science shows. Apologists need to be familiar with the current state of cosmological thought (as well as common misunderstandings of the Big Bang) and avoid misrepresenting current cosmological views.

Thus, they should not say that the Big Bang is proof that the universe had an absolute beginning. While the Big Bang is consistent with an absolute beginning, cosmologists have not been able to rule out options like there being a prior universe.

One way apologists have dealt with this concern is to point to the Borde-Guth-Vilenkin (BGV) theorem, which seeks to show that—on certain assumptions—even if there were one or more prior universes, there can’t be an unlimited number of them.

It’s fair to point to this theorem, but it would be a mistake for an apologist to present it as final proof, because the theorem depends on certain assumptions (e.g., that the universe has—on average—been expanding throughout its history) that cannot be taken for granted.

Further, apologists should be aware that authors of the theorem—Alan Guth and Alexander Vilenkin—do not agree that it shows the universe had to have a beginning. Guth apparently believes that the universe does not have a beginning, and Vilenkin states that all the theorem shows is that the expansion of the universe had to have a beginning, not the universe itself.

It thus would misrepresent the BGV theorem as showing that the scientific community has concluded that the universe had to have a beginning, even if it were before the Big Bang. (It also would be apologetically dangerous and foolish to do so, as the facts I’ve just mentioned could be thrown in the apologist’s face, discrediting him before his audience.)

Most fundamentally, the findings of science are always provisional, and the history of science contains innumerable cases where scientific opinion as reversed as new evidence has been found.

Consequently, apologists should never sell Big Bang cosmology—or any other aspect of science—as final “proof.”

This does not mean that apologists can’t appeal to scientific evidence. When the findings of science point in the direction aspects of the Faith, it is entirely fair to point that out. They just must not be oversold.

 

The Philosophical Approach

Prior to the mid-20th century, Big Bang cosmology had not been developed, and the scientific approach to defending the Kalaam argument’s second premise was not available.

Consequently, earlier discussions relied on philosophical arguments to try to show that the universe must have a beginning.

Such arguments remain a major part of the discussion today, and new philosophical ways of defending the second premise have been proposed.

Authors have different opinions about how well these work, but in studying them, I find myself agreeing with St. Thomas Aquinas that they do not. Thus far, I have not discovered any philosophical argument—ancient or modern—that I thought proved its case.

This is not to say that they don’t have superficial appeal. They do; otherwise, people wouldn’t propose them.

But when one thinks them through carefully, they all contain hidden flaws that keep them from succeeding—some of which are being discussed in this series.

I thus do not rely on philosophical arguments in my own presentation of the Kalaam argument.

 

Conclusion

The Kalaam cosmological argument is a valid and sound argument. It does prove that the universe has a cause, which can meaningfully be called God.

As a result, it can be used by apologists, and its simplicity makes it particularly attractive.

I use it myself, such as in my short, popular-level book The Words of Eternal Life.

However, the argument needs to be presented carefully. The scientific evidence we currently have is consistent with and suggestive of the world having a beginning in the finite past, though this evidence must not be oversold.

The philosophical arguments for the universe having a beginning are much more problematic. I do not believe that the ones developed to date work, and so I do not use them.

I thus advise other apologists to think carefully before doing so and to rigorously test these arguments: Seek out counterarguments, carefully consider them, and see if you can show why the arguments don’t work.

It is not enough that we find an argument convenient or initially plausible. We owe it to the truth, and honesty in doing apologetics compels us not to use arguments just because we want them to be true.

Presentism and Infinite History

“In the beginning, God created the heavens and the earth.” While the world definitely had a beginning, there’s a question of whether we can prove this by reason alone (i.e., by philosophical arguments).

Defenders of the Kalaam cosmological argument often use an argument like this one, which is found in William Lane Craig’s book Reasonable Faith:

1) An actually infinite number of things cannot exist.

2) A beginningless series of events in time entails an actually infinite number of things.

3) Therefore, a beginningless series of events in time cannot exist.

I have a problem with the first premise, but that’s a topic for another time. Here I’d like to look at Craig’s second premise.

Is it true that a beginningless series of events entails an actually infinite number of things?

At first glance, the answer would seem to be yes, but the reality is more complex.

 

The Nature of Time

The answer depends on your view of time. Here we need to consider two major theories of time, which are known as eternalism and presentism.

Eternalism holds that all of time exists. The past, the present, and the future are all real from the ultimate perspective—that is, from the eternal perspective outside of time. We may only experience history one bit at a time, but from the “eternal now” that God dwells in, all moments of time are equally real.

Presentism (as we will be using the term) holds that, from the ultimate perspective, the only time that exists is right now—the present. The past used to be real, but it is no longer. And the future will exist, but it does not yet. Since neither the past nor the future are real, they do not exist in any sense of the word. If you asked God—from his ultimate perspective—“What is real in the created order?” he would answer, “Only the present.”

 

The Eternalist Option

Supposing that eternalism is true, Craig’s second premise would be true. From the eternal perspective outside of time, God would see an infinite series of past events laid out before him.

Or, if you wish to avoid the question of how God’s knowledge works then, as the Creator, God would be causing that infinite series of past events to exist.

They would all be equally real—equally actual—from his perspective, and—since they have no beginning—they would be infinite. Being both actual and infinite, the events of a beginningless history would represent an actual infinity. Thus, the second premise would be true.

But for a classical Christian theist, there would be a problem, because Christianity teaches that God will give people endless life. While human beings may come into existence at the moment of their conception, they will never pass out of existence.

Therefore, humans have an endless future. And that future also will be equally real to God.

From his eternal perspective outside of time, God sees and creates all the moments of our endless future. They are both real—actual—from his perspective, and they are infinite in number. Being both actual and infinite, the moments of our future also would be an actual infinity.

From the viewpoint of a classical Christian theist, eternalism implies the existence of an actual infinity of future moments, giving such theists reason to challenge Craig’s first premise (that an actual infinity can’t exist).

However, this post is only examining his second premise, so let’s consider the other option we need to look at.

 

The Presentist Option

If only the present exists, is it true that a beginningless series of events in time entails an actually infinite number of things?

No. At least not an actual infinity of real things.

The reason is that, on the presentist view, only one moment of time exists. No past moments exist, and no future moments exist.

It doesn’t matter how many events took place in the past, because those events are no longer real. As soon as a new moment arrived, all the events taking place in the previous moment evaporated and are no longer actual.

Therefore, it doesn’t matter how many past events there have been—it could be a finite number or an infinite number—because they have all ceased to be actual. The only actual events are those occurring in the present.

So, if presentism is true, the second premise of Craig’s argument is false if applied to concrete, real things like events. A beginningless series of events in time does not entail an actually infinite number of such things because those things are no longer actual.

For a collection of things to be actually infinite, they all have to be actual from some perspective. On eternalism, that can happen, because all the moments of time are actual from the eternal perspective outside of time.

But it can’t happen on presentism, because this view holds that, from the ultimate perspective, only one moment is real, and one is a finite number. This view entails that no actual infinity of moments in time exists, because only one moment of time is actual.

This is why Aristotle could believe that the world did have an infinite history. Even though he thought an actually infinite number of things couldn’t exist at the same time, history didn’t present that problem, because one moment passed out of existence when another came into it, so the total number of moments was always finite.

 

The Counting Argument

In the Blackwell Companion to Natural Theology, Craig and coauthor James Sinclair respond to this issue with two lines of thought.

The first is based on counting, and their reasoning (omitting examples for brevity) goes like this:

[W]e may take it as a datum that the presentist can accurately count things that have existed but no longer exist. . . .

The nonexistence of such things or events is no hindrance to their being enumerated. . . .

So in a beginningless series of past events of equal duration, the number of past events must be infinite, for it is larger than any natural number. . . .

[I]f we consider all the events in an infinite temporal regress of events, they constitute an actual infinite.

It’s true that a presentist can count things that have existed but no longer exist (e.g., the number of days that have elapsed so far this year)—and their nonexistence doesn’t prevent this counting (just look at a calendar!).

The problem comes in the third statement, because it can be understood in more than one way.

In terms of what is real on the presentist view, the number of past events is not infinite, because no past events exist. That’s a key point of presentism.

If you want to talk about an infinite number of past events, you have to shift from speaking of events that do exist to those that have existed, and those aren’t the same thing.

Yes, on presentism, we could speak of an infinite collection of events that were real but aren’t anymore. And that’s the point: They aren’t real.

This points to a second way of reading the statement when Craig and Sinclair speak of “the number of past events.”

If we are talking about the number of events, then we’re no longer talking about the events themselves. Instead, we’re talking about a number, which raises a question.

 

What Are Numbers?

Mathematicians and philosophers have a variety of views about what numbers are. Some classify them as “abstract objects” that exist independent of the mind. Others think of them as mental constructs of some kind. There are many variations on these views.

Whatever the case may be, Craig doesn’t see infinite numbers themselves being a problem.

In his talks and writings, he has frequently said that he doesn’t have a problem with the mathematics of infinity—that modern mathematical concepts dealing with the infinite are fine and useful as concepts. Thus, the infinite set of natural numbers (0, 1, 2, 3 . . . ) is a useful concept.

Craig doesn’t reject the idea that the set of natural numbers is actually infinite. It’s just not the kind of actual infinity that causes a problem for him because numbers aren’t concrete objects in the real world.

So, actual infinities of the numerical order are fine, in which case it’s fine if the number of past events is actually infinite. It’s an actual infinity of events themselves that he says can’t be part of the real world.

And on presentism, they’re not. Past events would have to be understood in some other way. They might be abstract objects, like many mathematicians hold numbers to be. Or they might be purely mental concepts at this point, as others regard numbers.

Whatever is the case, on presentism they do not exist in the real world. And so, whatever kind of infinity a beginningless universe would involve, it doesn’t violate the principle that—while actual infinities may exist in an abstract way, as in mathematics—they don’t exist in the real world.

 

Back to the Future

There is another way of illustrating the problem with the argument from counting, and it involves considering the number of future events.

If the universe can’t have a beginningless past because an infinite set of non-real past events can’t exist, then we also can’t have an endless future, because that entails an infinite set of non-real future events.

The argument simply involves shifting from events that used to be real to those that will be real.

If God gives people endless life, then the number of days that we will experience in the future is infinite. As the hymn says about heaven,

When we’ve been there ten thousand years,

Bright shining as the sun,

We’ve no less days to sing God’s praise,

Than when we first begun.

As Craig and Sinclair acknowledge:

It might rightly be pointed out that on presentism there are no future events and so no series of future events. Therefore, the number of future events is simply zero. . . . [O]n presentism, the past is as unreal as the future and, therefore, the number of past events could, with equal justification, be said to be zero. It might be said that at least there have been past events, and so they can be numbered. But by the same token there will be future events, so why can they not be numbered? Accordingly, one might be tempted to say that in an endless future there will be an actually infinite number of events, just as in a beginningless past there have been an actually infinite number of events.

So, why should an infinite number of future events be considered more permissible for a presentist than an infinite number of past ones?

 

Possible vs. Actual Infinity

Craig and Sinclair’s response involves the difference between an actual infinity (where an unlimited number of elements exist simultaneously) and a potential infinity (where an unlimited number of elements don’t exist simultaneously). They write:

[T]here never will be an actually infinite number of [future] events since it is impossible to count to infinity. The only sense in which there will be an infinite number of events is that the series of events will go toward infinity as a limit. But that is the concept of a potential infinite, not an actual infinite. Here the objectivity of temporal becoming makes itself felt. For as a result of the arrow of time, the series of events later than any arbitrarily selected past event is properly to be regarded as potentially infinite, that is to say, finite but indefinitely increasing toward infinity as a limit.

This reasoning is mistaken. It is false to say that “the series of events later than any arbitrarily selected past event is . . . finite but indefinitely increasing toward infinity as a limit.”

No. If you arbitrarily select any event in time and consider the sequence of later events, they do not “indefinitely increase toward infinity.” They are always infinite.

Consider January 1, 1900. On the Christian view, how many days of endless life will there be after that? An infinite number.

Consider January 1, 2000. How many days are to come? Again, an infinite number.

Consider January 1, 2100. How many days follow? Still an infinite number.

As the hymn says, “We’ve no less days to sing God’s praise than when we first begun!”

What Craig and Sinclair are thinking of is the fact that, if you pick a date and go any arbitrary distance into the future, your destination will still be a finite number of days from your starting point.

Thus, the number of days that has elapsed between the start and finish of your journey grows toward infinity but never gets there, making this span of days a potential rather than actual infinity.

But it does not follow—and is simply wrong—that the complete set of future days is only potentially infinite. To show this, just give each day a number: Today is 0, tomorrow is 1, the next day is 2, and so on. We can thus map the set of future days onto the set of natural numbers, which is actually rather than potentially infinite.

Take any day you like, and on the Christian view the quantity of days that will be after it is identical to the quantity of natural numbers.

The quantity of days that will be—like the quantity of natural numbers—does not grow. This quantity just is.

Unless you say—contrary to the teaching of the Christian faith—that the number of future days is finite and God won’t give us endless life, then there is an actual infinity of future days.

And if a presentist wants to affirm an actual infinity of currently-not-real days that will be, he must allow the possibility of an actual infinity of currently-not-real days that have been.

 

Conclusion

In summary, Craig’s second premise was:

2) A beginningless series of events in time entails an actually infinite number of things.

Whether this is true will depend on one’s view of time and the status of non-real things.

On eternalism, a beginningless series of events in time would involve an actually infinite number of things, for all these moments exist from God’s perspective outside of time. But so would the actually infinite number of future days that God promises us, giving the eternalist reason to reject the idea that an actual infinity cannot exist in the real world.

On presentism, a beginningless series of events in time would not involve an actual infinity of events existing in the real world, because presentism holds that the past does not exist.

Such a series of events might result in an actual infinity of (past) non-existent days, but so would the actual infinity of (future) non-existent days. And if a Christian allows one set of non-existent days, the other must be allowed as well.

The fact that the past days are countable is irrelevant, because so are the future days.

And it is simply false to say that the days that will be are only potentially infinite. They’re not. Right now, the number of days that will be is actually infinite, the same way the set of natural numbers is actually infinite.

Based on what we’ve seen here, presentism does not exclude an infinite past any more than it does an infinite future.

Traversing an Infinite?

God created the universe a finite time ago, but there’s a question of whether we can prove this by reason alone.

Defenders of the Kalaam cosmological argument often claim that the universe cannot have an infinite history because “traversing an infinite” is impossible.

In his book Reasonable Faith (pp. 120-124), William Lane Craig puts the argument this way

1. The series of events in time is a collection formed by adding one member after another

2. A collection formed by adding one member after another cannot be actually infinite

3. Therefore, the series of events in time cannot be actually infinite.

The second premise of this argument is the one that deals with “traversing an infinite.” Craig writes:

Sometimes this problem is described as the impossibility of traversing the infinite.

Still a third way of describing it is saying that you can’t form infinity “by successive addition.”

Whatever expression you prefer, each of these expressions refer to the intuition people commonly have about infinity—that “you can’t get there from here.”

 

Where Is “Here”?

If you can’t get to infinity from here, where is “here”?

However you want to phrase the problem—getting there from here, traversing an infinite, or successive addition, this is a question that needs to be answered.

Let’s take another look at the second premise:

2. A collection formed by adding one member after another cannot be actually infinite

What does it mean to “form” a collection by adding one member after another?

Perhaps the most natural way to take this would be to form such a collection from nothing. That is, you start with zero elements in the collection (or maybe one element) and then successively add one new member after another.

And it’s quite true that, if you form a collection this way, you will never arrive at an infinite number of members. No matter how many elements you add to the collection, one at a time, the collection will always have a finite number of elements.

This can be seen through a simple counting exercise. If you start with 0 and then keep adding +1, you’ll get the standard number line:

0, 1, 2, 3, 4, 5, 6, 7 . . .

But no matter how many times you add +1, the resulting number will always be finite—just one unit larger than the previous finite number.

However, there is a problem . . .

 

The First-and-Last Fallacy

As I’ve discussed elsewhere, any string of natural numbers that has both a first and a last element is—by definition—finite.

Any time you specify a first natural number and a last natural number, the space between them is limited.

It thus would be fallacious reasoning to envision an infinite timeline with both first and last elements.

Yet it is very easy to let the idea of an infinite past having a beginning somewhere “infinitely far back” unintentionally sneak back into discussions of the Kalaam argument.

It can easily happen without people being aware of it, and often our language is to blame:

  • The natural sense of the word “traverse” suggests going from one point to another, suggesting both a beginning point and an end point.
  • So does the idea of “forming” an infinite collection. If we imagine forming a collection, we naturally envision starting with nothing (a collection with no members) and then adding things to it.
  • And if we think of getting to infinity “from here,” we naturally think of a starting point in the finite realm (“here”) and an end point (“infinity”).

Without at all meaning to, it’s thus very easy to fall into the trap of subconsciously supposing both a starting point and an ending point in a supposedly infinite history.

This happens often enough that I’ve called it the First-and-Last Fallacy.

 

Taking No Beginning Seriously

In Reasonable Faith, Craig denies that this is how his argument should be understood. He writes:

Mackie and Sobel object that this sort of argument illicitly presupposes an infinitely distant starting point in the past and then pronounces it impossible to travel from that point to today. But if the past is infinite, they say, then there would be no starting point whatever, not even an infinitely distant one. Nevertheless, from any given point in the past, there is only a finite distance to the present, which is easily “traversed.” But in fact no proponent of the kalam argument of whom I am aware has assumed that there was an infinitely distant starting point in the past. The fact that there is no beginning at all, not even an infinitely distant one, seems only to make the problem worse, not better (boldface added).

Craig thus wishes us to understand his argument not as forming an infinite collection of past historical moments from an infinitely distant starting point—i.e., from a beginning.

It’s good that he is clear on this, because otherwise his second premise would commit the First-and-Last Fallacy.

But does this really make things worse rather than better?

It would seem not.

 

Formed from What?

If we are not to envision a collection being “formed” from nothing by successive addition, then it must obviously be formed from something. Namely, it must be formed from another, already existing collection.

For example, suppose I have a complete run of my favorite comic book, The Legion of Super-Heroes. Let’s say that, as of the current month, it consists of issue #1 to issue #236.

Then, next month, issue #237 comes out, so I purchase it and add it to my collection. I now have a new, larger collection that was “formed” by adding one new member to my previous collection.

Now let’s apply that to the situation of an infinite history. Suppose that the current moment—“now”—is the last element of an infinite collection of previous moments (with no beginning moment).

How was this collection formed?

Obviously, it was formed from a previous collection that included all of the past moments except the current one.

Let’s give these things some names:

  • Let P be the collection of all the past moments
  • Let 1 represent the current moment
  • And let E represent the collection of all the moments that have ever existed

With those terms in place, it’s clear that:

P + 1 = E

We thus can form one collection (E) from another collection (P) by adding a member to it.

 

But Can It Be Infinite?

Now we come to Craig’s second premise, which said that you can’t form an actually infinite collection by adding one member after another.

If you imagine forming the collection from nothing—and thus commit the First-and-Last Fallacy—then this is true.

But it’s not true if you avoid the fallacy and imagine forming an actually infinite collection from a previous collection by adding to it.

The previous collection just needs to be actually infinite as well. If P is an actually infinite collection and you add 1 to it, E will be actually infinite as well.

And this is what we find in the case of an infinite past. Let us envision an infinite past as the set of all negative numbers, ending in the present, “0” moment:

. . . -7, -6, -5, -4, -3, -2, -1, 0.

The set of all the numbers below 0 is infinite, but so is the set of all numbers below -1, all the numbers below -2, and so on. Each of these collections is actually infinite, and so we can form a new, actually infinite set by taking one of them and adding a new member to it.

Understood this way, Craig’s second premise is simply false. You can form an actually infinite collection by adding new members to an actually infinite collection—which is what we would have in the case of a universe with an infinite past, one that really does not have a starting point.

 

Conclusion

What we make of Craig’s argument will depend on how we take its second premise.

Taken in what may be the most natural way (forming an infinite collection from nothing—or from any finite amount—by successive addition), will result in the argument committing the First-and-Last Fallacy.

But if we take it in the less obvious way (forming an infinite collection by adding to an already infinite collection), then the second premise is simply false.

There may be other grounds—other arguments—by which one might try to show that the universe cannot have an infinite past.

But the argument from “successive addition,” “traversing an infinite,” or “getting there from here” does not work.

Depending on how you interpret it, the argument either commits a fallacy or uses a false premise.

Who Was the Man Who Ran Away Naked?

Mark contains a brief story not found in the other Gospels. Immediately after Jesus’ arrest, the Eleven scatter, and we read:

And a certain young man was following him, clothed only in a linen cloth on his naked body. And they attempted to seize him, but he left behind the linen cloth and fled naked (14:51-52, LEB).

People naturally want to know who this young, anonymous man was.

 

Was it Mark?

Today, many say it was Mark himself—that he recorded this incident the way medieval artists sometimes put tiny portraits of themselves in their paintings or the way Alfred Hitchcock briefly appears in his films.

Some may even suppose this is the traditional answer that has always been believed, but it’s not. The Church Fathers made other proposals, and this theory only became common in the late 19th century.

There also are problems with it. One is that the Greek word for “young man” (neaniskos) indicates a man who is past puberty and thus in his late teens or early 20s.

But when we meet Mark in Acts 12:12, it is the year A.D. 43—a decade after the Crucifixion—and it appears that Mark is a young man then, not one pushing or over 30.

We also have testimony from a first century figure named John the Presbyter, who says Mark “had not heard the Lord, nor had he followed him” during his ministry (Eusebius, Church History 3:39:15).

Finally, we don’t have evidence of an ancient literary tradition of authors giving themselves brief, anonymous appearances in their works. That isn’t what Mark’s audience would expect, so this theory reads a much later artistic and cinematic technique into ancient literature.

 

A Curious Stranger?

Another proposal is that this was a random person—not a member of the Christian community—who happened to be following out of curiosity and got nabbed.

This isn’t impossible, but the argument for it is weak. The argument is that people normally wore two garments, an inner one and an outer one. So, perhaps the young man was asleep, heard the noise, quickly put on a single garment, and when to see what the commotion was.

The problem is that people also sometimes wore just one garment, so the man was not clearly underdressed.

Further, if he were not a Christian, why would the authorities grab him? Mark tells us that “a crowd” was present for the arrest (14:43), and a person walking along with the crowd would not be grabbed unless he previously had been seen among Jesus’ followers.

Also, if this man had no connection with the Christian community, how did this story get preserved? The way Mark tells it, the Eleven had already fled, and the arresting party would have no reason to tell the story to the Christian community later on.

The preservation of the story—and its use by Mark—would be more logical if the person was known to the Evangelist and his audience.

In that case, the question would be: Why isn’t his name mentioned?

 

Protective Anonymity

Scholars have noted that, in the Synoptic Gospels, certain people remain curiously anonymous in the Passion narrative.

These include the woman who anoints Jesus (Mark 14:3), the owner of the house where Jesus eats the Last Supper (14:14-15), and the disciple who strikes off the ear of the high priest’s servant (14:47).

What these figures have in common is that they committed acts that would be considered seditious by the Jerusalem authorities. The woman anointed Jesus, which could be seen as consecrating him for his role as the anointed Messiah, the king of the Jews. The householder then hosts the new rebel king. And the last takes up arms in defense of the rebel king.

When the story of Jesus’ Passion was first being told in the Jerusalem church, it would not be safe to publicly name these people—not if they still lived in or visited Jerusalem, where the Jewish authorities could get them.

Neither would it do to write their names in a Gospel that would find its way to the Jerusalem church. So, the theory is that the Synoptic Evangelists give these people “protective anonymity.”

But when John was written, the individuals may have moved away, died, or already been taken into custody, so they didn’t need protection.

That’s why some are named in John. The woman who anoints Jesus is revealed to be Mary the sister of Lazarus (John 12:3), and the disciple who wielded the sword is revealed to be St. Peter (John 18:10).

But their identities were known in the Christian community from the beginning. Jesus had said, concerning Mary, “wherever the gospel is proclaimed in the whole world, what she has done will also be told in memory of her” (Mark 14:9), and when Peter was preaching the gospel orally, he would have identified himself as the man with the sword.

Yet in Mark, Mary is simply “a woman” (14:3) and Peter is “a certain one of the bystanders” (14:47).

 

Someone we know?

Could Mark be withholding the identity of the “certain young man,” though it was known to the Christian community? Might we have heard of him? If so, who might it be?

St. Ambrose suggested that it might be John son of Zebedee, but it’s hard to see why he would need protective anonymity. People knew he was one of the Twelve, and Mark names him as present at the time of the arrest (14:33). He already was in danger as a known supporter of Jesus, and merely escaping an arrest was not a seditious act.

Theophylact of Ohrid suggested the man might be James the “brother” of the Lord. However, Jesus’ brethren didn’t believe in him during his ministry (John 7:5), so he was unlikely to be following Jesus that night.

Some have proposed that the “beloved disciple” was actually John the Presbyter, who was from an aristocratic Jerusalem family and personally knew the high priest. He may have been the host of the Last Supper, which is why he was seated next to Jesus (John 13:23).

If so, there could be reason to shield his identity, and he never names himself in the Gospel!

However, he doesn’t identify himself as the man who ran away. And, after Jesus is arrested, he follows Jesus to the high priest’s house and even gets Peter access to the courtyard (18:15-16). This makes it unlikely he had just escaped arrest.

 

The ideal candidate?

The ideal candidate for the young man would be someone who (a) was not one of the Twelve, (b) lived in the Jerusalem area, (c) was a follower of Jesus, and (d) was already wanted by the authorities, since he doesn’t do anything criminal in Mark.

Is there such a person? Yes, and it’s Lazarus. Immediately after John records Mary anointing Jesus, he says:

When the great crowd of the Jews learned that he was there, they came, not only on account of Jesus but also to see Lazarus, whom he had raised from the dead.

So the chief priests planned to put Lazarus also to death, because on account of him many of the Jews were going away and believing in Jesus (12:9-11).

The authorities thus were already looking to kill Lazarus. But he may not have known this, which could explain why he thought it would be safe to follow, only to be seized and forced to flee naked.

Lazarus—like his sister Mary—was known to the early Christian community, and when the Passion was retold in the Jerusalem church, people would have known the parts they played. Yet, it wouldn’t have been safe to name them publicly, such as in a Gospel, as long as they remained alive and in the Jerusalem area.

This doesn’t prove Lazarus was the man who ran away naked, but it fits the evidence, and it’s an intriguing possibility!

The Kalam Cosmological Argument

This page collects articles I have been writing dealing with the Kalaam cosmological argument for God’s existence. It is expected to grow over time as I write more on the subject.

Put simply, the argument goes:

  1. Whatever has a beginning has a cause.
  2. The universe has a beginning.
  3. Therefore, the universe has a cause.

The cause of the universe can be meaningfully described as God. Therefore, God exists.

This argument is both valid and sound–that is, it uses a valid logical form and its premises are true, so its conclusion is true.

Despite this, many of the arguments used to support it are not successful. In particular, many of the philosophical arguments used for its second premise are flawed.

Here are articles in which I explore why.

General Considerations:

The Big Bang and Science

Philosophical Arguments:

The First Argument (No Actual Infinities):

The Second Argument (No Infinity by Successive Addition):

More Recent Arguments:

Related:

What’s Wrong with the Countdown Paradox?

Sometimes defenders of the Kalaam cosmological argument defend its second premise (i.e., that the world couldn’t have an infinite past) by proposing a paradox involving counting.

The line of reasoning goes something like this:

A. Suppose that the universe has an infinite history (the kind of history you’d need to do an infinite countdown).

B. Suppose that a person has been counting down the infinite set of negative numbers (. . . -3, -2, -1) for all eternity, and they finish today, so today’s number is 0. It took them an infinite amount of time to reach 0 in the present.

C. Now suppose that we go back in time to yesterday. How much time was there before yesterday? Also an infinite amount of time! Given that, they could have counted down the infinite set of negative numbers so that they reached 0 yesterday instead of today!

D. So, we have a paradox: If the person had been counting down the negative numbers for all eternity, they could have finished today—or yesterday—or on any other day in the past, since there was always an infinite number of days before that.

E. There needs to be a sufficient reason why they stop on the day they did.

The Kalaam defender then challenges the Kalaam skeptic to name the sufficient reason, and if he’s not convinced by the answer, he rejects Step A of the argument—the idea that the universe has an infinite history—since there doesn’t seem to be anything wrong with Steps B, C, D, or E.

What’s problematic about this line of reasoning?

 

Arbitrary Labels

To see what the answer is, we need to think about the arbitrariness of the labels involved in the countdown.

In Part B, the Kalaam defender chose to use the set of negative numbers, but he could have chosen something else.

For example, he could have chosen the digits of the irrational number pi (3.14159 . . . ) in reverse order (. . . 9, 5, 1, 4, 1, 3), in which case today’s number would be 3.

Or he could have used the Golden Ratio and chosen the digits of the irrational number phi (1.61803 . . . ) and reversed them, in which case today’s number would be 1.

Or he could have picked anything else, such as an infinitely long string of random numbers—or random words—or random symbols.

Any string will do for an infinite count of the past—as long as it’s an infinitely long string.

The point we learn from this is that the labels we apply to particular days are arbitrary. It depends entirely on what labels we choose. We can pick any labels we want and use them for any set of days we want.

 

Forward Counts

To underscore this point, let’s consider counts that go forward in time rather than backwards.

For example, we could choose the set of natural numbers (0, 1, 2, 3 . . . ), assigning 0 to today, 1 to tomorrow, 2 to the day after that, and so on.

Or we could use the digits of pi, in which case today would be 3, tomorrow 1, the day after that 4, etc.

Or the digits of phi, so today would be 1, tomorrow 6, the day after that 1, etc.

Or we could use something else—such as an infinite string of random numbers, words, or symbols.

We can pick whatever labels for a set of days, beginning with today, that we want!

 

A Count-Up Paradox

Now consider the following line of reasoning:

A*. Suppose that the universe has an infinite future (the kind of future you’d need to do an infinite count going forwards).

B*. Suppose that a person starts counting the infinite set of natural numbers (0, 1, 2, 3 . . . ) today, so that today’s number is 0, tomorrow’s is 1, the next day is 2, etc.

C*. Now suppose that we go forward in time to tomorrow. How much time is there left in the future of the universe? Also an infinite amount of time! Given that, the person could start their count of the infinite set of whole numbers so that they begin with 0 tomorrow instead of today!

D*. So, we have a paradox: If the person counts the set of whole numbers for all eternity, they could have started today—or tomorrow—or on any other day in the future, since there will always be an infinite number of days after that.

E*. There needs to be a sufficient reason why they start on the day they do.

If we’re challenged to name the sufficient reason why the person starts counting on the day they do, what will our answer be?

Mine would be, “Because that’s how you set up the thought experiment! You made this determination in Step B*. You could have chosen to start the count on any day you wanted (today, tomorrow, yesterday—or any other day), and you chose the set of numbers that would be used to label these days. Your choices are the sufficient reason for why the count starts and why it labels the days the way it does.”

 

Turn About Is Fair Play

And this is the answer to the original line of reasoning we presented. The same logic is present in A-E that is present in A*-E*, so the answer is the same.

The reason that the original countdown stopped today, which was labelled 0, is because those were the choices made in Step B. The person setting up the thought experiment chose that the countdown stop today, and he chose that it would stop with 0.

Once again, it is the choices that the person made that determine when the count stops and what it stops on.

There is only a “paradox” here if you lose sight of the fact that these choices were made and demand a sufficient reason over and above them.

To say—in the first case—“I know I made these choices in Step B, but I want a reason over and above that to explain why the countdown doesn’t stop on another day” is the same as saying—in the second case—“I know I made these choices in Step B*, but I want a reason over and above that to explain why the count doesn’t start on another day.”

No such reasons are needed. The choices made in Step B are sufficient to explain why the countdown works the way it does, just as the choices made in Step B* are sufficient to explain why the count-up works the way it does.

So, like a lot of paradoxes, the “countdown paradox” has a perfectly obvious solution once you think about it.

 

God as the Decider

Now let’s apply this to the question of whether God could have created the universe with an infinite past. In this case, we’re doing a thought experiment where God is the one making the choices.

A**. Suppose that God creates a universe with an infinite past (the kind you need for an infinite countdown).

B**. Suppose that–within this timeline–God creates a person (or angel, or computer, or whatever) that counts down the negative numbers so that he finishes today, and today’s number is 0.

Why didn’t the person stop counting on some other day or with some other number? Because that’s not what God chose. He chose to have it happen this way, with the person counting the number -2 two days ago, the number -1 one day ago, and the number 0 today.

Could he have have done it differently? Absolutely! God could have made different choices!

In fact–to go beyond what we’ve stated thus far–God may have created other people doing just that.

C**. Suppose that God also created a second person who has been counting for all eternity such that he ended yesterday with the number 0.

D**. Suppose that God further created a third person who has been counting for all eternity such that he ended two days ago with the number 0.

These are also possible, and we can modify our thought experiment such that God creates any number of people we like, finishing an infinite count on any day we like, with any number (or word or symbol) we like.

In each case, it is God’s choice that is the sufficient reason why the person finished when he did and with what he did.

The situation is parallel to the following:

A***. Suppose that God creates a universe with an infinite future (the kind you need to do an infinite count going forward).

B***. Suppose that–within this timeline–God creates a person who starts an infinite count today, beginning with the number 0.

As before, we can include any number of counters we want:

C***. Suppose that God also creates a second person who begins counting tomorrow, starting with the number 0.

D***. Suppose that God further creates a third person who begins counting the day after tomorrow, starting with the number 0.

As before, we can modify our thought experiment to include any number of counters we want, they can start on any day we want, and they can start with whatever number (or word or symbol) that we want.

Yet in these scenarios, it is God’s choices that determine who is created, when they start counting, and how the count works. These choices are the only reasons we need to explain what is happening.

If there is no unsolvable paradox preventing the scenarios described in A***-D***, then there is no unsolvable paradox preventing the scenarios described in A**-D**–or in any of the previous scenarios we’ve covered.

There just is no problem with the idea of a person doing an infinite countdown ending today–any more than there is with the idea of a person beginning an infinite countdown today.