Pope Francis Celebrates Blaise Pascal

The French mathematician, philosopher, and apologist Blaise Pascal (1623-1662) was born 400 years ago. The anniversary of his birth was recently celebrated by Pope Francis in an apostolic letter titled Sublimitas et Miseria Hominis (“The Grandeur and Misery of Man”)—reflecting one of the themes in Pascal’s writing.

Recent popes, such as John Paul II and Benedict XVI, have expressed appreciation for Pascal, and in 2017 Pope Francis reportedly said that he “deserves beatification.”

The pope’s 5,400-word apostolic letter makes for interesting reading. Papal documents like this are commonly ghost written, and the pope then makes the words his own when he signs and issues the document. The same is presumably true of this letter, and it is clear that whoever drafted it knows Pascal’s life and thought very well. It’s a quality read!

At least in Catholic circles, Pascal is best known today for two things: his Provincial Letters, which are a defense of the Jansenists against their Jesuit opponents, and his Pensees (French, “Thoughts”), which consists of notes that he took in preparation for an apology defending the Christian faith that he wanted to write.

However, these writings come from the later period of Pascal’s life, and he is remembered outside Catholic circles for other contributions. As the letter notes, “In 1642, at the age of nineteen, he invented an arithmetic machine, the ancestor of our modern computers.”

Pascal also made contributions in other areas, including physics (specifically, fluid dynamics, where he proposed what is now known as Pascal’s law) and mathematics (where he made numerous contributions, including being one of the founders of probability theory).

Pope Francis’s apostolic letter touches briefly on such contributions, but it focuses on the development of Pascal’s life and his Christian faith, which became more prominent as he got older.

A turning point in this regard occurred on the night of Monday, November 23, 1654, when Pascal was 31-years old. For two hours—between 10:30 p.m. and 12:30 a.m.—he had a profound mystical experience that led to a religious conversion.

Afterward, he wrote an intimate series of thoughts about this experience on a sheet of paper. How meaningful the experience was to him is illustrated by the fact that he thereafter carried the paper with him, keeping it in the lining of his coat, where it was discovered after his death.

What we know about this powerful mystical experience comes from the brief, tantalizing statements he made on the paper. It is now known as Pascal’s Memorial, and an English translation is available here.

Pope Francis’s letter discusses the Provincial Letters and the Jansenist controversy that occasioned them. Since the Jesuits were the target of the Provincial Letters, it is interesting to see what Francis—the first Jesuit pope—has to say. He writes:

Before concluding, I must mention Pascal’s relationship to Jansenism. One of his sisters, Jacqueline, had entered religious life in Port-Royal, in a religious congregation the theology of which was greatly influenced by Cornelius Jansen, whose treatise Augustinus appeared in 1640. In January 1655, following his “night of fire” [i.e., his mystical experience], Pascal made a retreat at the abbey of Port-Royal. In the months that followed, an important and lengthy dispute about the Augustinus arose between Jesuits and “Jansenists” at the Sorbonne, the university of Paris. The controversy dealt chiefly with the question of God’s grace and the relationship between grace and human nature, specifically our free will. Pascal, while not a member of the congregation of Port-Royal, nor given to taking sides—as he wrote, “I am alone. . . . I am not at all part of Port-Royal”—was charged by the Jansenists to defend them, given his outstanding rhetorical skill. He did so in 1656 and 1657, publishing a series of eighteen writings known as The Provincial Letters.

Although several propositions considered “Jansenist” were indeed contrary to the faith, a fact that Pascal himself acknowledged, he maintained that those propositions were not present in the Augustinus or held by those associated with Port-Royal. Even so, some of his own statements, such as those on predestination, drawn from the later theology of Augustine and formulated more severely by Jansen, do not ring true. We should realize, however, that, just as Saint Augustine sought in the fifth century to combat the Pelagians, who claimed that man can, by his own powers and without God’s grace, do good and be saved, so Pascal, for his part, sincerely believed that he was battling an implicit pelagianism or semipelagianism in the teachings of the “Molinist” Jesuits, named after the theologian Luis de Molina, who had died in 1600 but was still quite influential in the middle of the seventeenth century. Let us credit Pascal with the candor and sincerity of his intentions.

Pope Francis also touches on Pascal’s apologetics and his famous work, the Pensees. Interestingly, he does not mention the most famous part of the Pensees, which is a passage in which Pascal seeks to help those who feel unable to choose between skepticism and Christianity based on evidence.

He proposes what has become known as Pascal’s Wager, in which he offers a way to use practical reason to decide between the options when an evidential solution seems unavailable. In essence, Pascal argues that if one adopts or “bets” on skepticism and it turns out that skepticism is true, then one will at most reap a finite benefit. However, if one “bets” on Christianity and it turns out that Christianity is true, then one will receive an infinite benefit. It is thus in one’s interest to wager that Christianity is true if one feels unable to decide based on the evidence.

It should be noted that the Wager is designed only to decide between Christianity and skepticism. However, Wager-like reasoning can be applied to other religious options. (For example, if one is deciding between reincarnation and the view we only have one life, it is better to wager that we only have one life, so we need to make this one count.)

Pascal experienced his final illness in 1662. Shortly before his death, he said that if the doctors were correct and he would recover, he would devote the rest of his life to serving the poor.

However, he did not recover, and he passed on to his reward at the age of 39. It is not clear what he died of, but tuberculosis and stomach cancer have been proposed.

It is good to see Pascal being recognized for his contributions. He was, indeed, a genius, as well as a man of profound faith and insight. He is well worth studying by contemporary apologists.

Is Objective Morality Real?

A reader writes:

I have been really hurting due to a question that I can’t seem to find an answer to wherever I look. Wherever I go, I can’t find a Christian that will answer my questions. I am Catholic, but this particular question causes me pain, because morality is the bedrock that my framework is built upon.

My question is, how do I know that Morality is real?

I heard that morality is just a herd mentality to ensure human survival. Like, for example, I don’t kill him, so he doesn’t kill me, a herd mentality. Homosexuality is wrong because it doesn’t ensure human survival. It’s a sort of empathy-like survival mechanism.

This does mean that if you do something wrong, since there would be no Objective Morality, that there is nothing actually wrong about it, and you could technically do whatever, and it would just be atoms moving across space-time, a scary thought indeed.

How do I beat moral nihilism? What are some arguments against it? What if someone is willing to accept it, because facts don’t care about your feelings? How do you show its real? What evidence is there? I still believe, but it hurts to have my framework attacked.

Those attacking the objective reality of morality based on its survival value are making a fundamental mistake, which is pitting objective morality and survival value against each other. They do not need to be seen in opposition and should be seen as in harmony.
According to the standard Christian understanding (and, specifically, the Catholic understanding), morality is rooted in human nature. For example, we need lifelong marriages because our offspring are born helpless and take 2 decades to mature. Therefore, they need care for decades, and thus the parents need to stay together for decades, which amounted to a full human lifespan before modern medicine. Therefore, human nature implies lifelong marital unions.
This would be different if God had designed us to be creatures like fish, which essentially fertilize their eggs and then leave them to their fate. No lifelong marriages would be needed.
We therefore must understand the rules of (human) morality in terms of human nature. They are given to us by God to help us survive and thrive, based on the way our natures work. Therefore, being a moral person has survival/flourishing value.
However, this is exactly what we would expect of a loving God in giving us his laws. They would be based around our nature and be meant to promote our good. They would thus draw upon our nature as human beings and make explicit the best ways for humans to survive and thrive.
God’s law for man thus is not an alien standard imposed on us that has nothing to do with human flourishing. Instead, on the Christian view, it is designed to promote human flourishing, based on our nature.
And this is what Scripture indicates: God gave man laws for man’s own good. The law is designed to help us. Following it is good for us.
This is explicit in various passages in the Bible. It’s also implicit in other passages. One that I find particularly interesting is James 1:22-25, which compares a person who hears God’s law and does not do it to a man who looks at his face in a mirror and then forgets what he looks like. The analogy James uses shows how God’s law reveals our own nature to us. If we forget God’s law, we forget our own nature.
The fact that morality has survival value thus is not contradictory to the biblical view of morality. It is built into the biblical view of morality. The biblical view presupposes that morality has survival value, and the two should not be put in opposition to each other.
When it comes to evidence for the objective existence of morality, we have the testimony of the human heart. Humans have a powerful intuition that some things are Just Right and other things are Just Wrong. Our hearts tell us that morality is objectively real (and they tell us this because God built it into us).
Even those who claim not to believe in objective morality inevitably slip back into assuming that it is real. They invariably fall back into the assumption that some things are just evil–whether it’s racism, sexism, torturing babies for fun, or whatever else it may be. They may be able to momentarily suspend their belief in objective morality, but they inevitably slip back into the view that it is real. So strong is the testimony of the human heart.
Further, belief in objective morality is a human universal. It appears in all world cultures in all periods of history. This only happens with things that are built into human nature, and so belief in morality is part of human nature.
We thus have powerful evidence from the human heart that morality is objectively real.
Furthermore, by believing in morality, we are simply going along with our nature (rather than fighting against it).
Finally, a critic of morality would have absolutely no grounds for trying to guilt us or cause us anxiety for our belief in morality, because if the critic was right then–on the critic’s own principles–we wouldn’t be doing anything wrong by believing in morality, because there would be no objective right or wrong.
And we’d be happier for just going with what human nature tells us–that morality is real.
We’d also reap the survival and flourishing benefits of leading a moral life.
I hope this helps, and God bless you!

Pascal’s Wager and Ethics

Pascal’s Wager is an argument proposed by the French philosopher and mathematician Blaise Pascal in his posthumously published work Pensées (1670).

Pascal proposed the wager as a method of helping a person torn between belief and unbelief in God when they don’t feel able to settle the question based on evidence.

As such, the wager is not an evidential or “cognitive” argument for belief in God. It is an example of practical or “non-cognitive” reasoning.

In essence, Pascal seeks to show that—whether or not God exists—it is in the interests of a person who is unable to decide between these options to go ahead and believe.

It thus offers practical reasons to believe rather than new evidence to believe.

I won’t go into the details of Pascal’s Wager, because I’ve written about it elsewhere (for example, here).

However, the wager relies on insights that can be useful in other situations, and I’d like to explore some of those here.

 

Context

First, we need to understand the context in which the wager was proposed and what its limitations are.

We’ve already mentioned that it is not designed to give new evidence. That’s the point of the wager. It’s meant to help someone who has reviewed the evidence and still feels unable to decide.

As a result, the wager turns to look at matters besides evidence—that is, what is in the person’s interest.

There is nothing wrong with interest-based, practical reason. Humans constantly make prudential judgments about what to do based on their interests: Is it in my interest to take this job or that? To marry this person or that? To watch this movie or that?

Making decisions that maximize our interests is a fundamental part of the human experience. Such reasoning is built into us.

 

An Objection: Proportion to Evidence

Some question whether it is legitimate to apply practical reason to matters of belief.

Some have claimed that we have a moral duty to proportion our beliefs strictly to the evidence we have supporting them.

It is difficult to know what advocates of this claim are envisioning, because this is not how humans work. We do not constantly review our beliefs and assign numerical probabilities to them.

Much less do we proportion the beliefs themselves, so that we would say, “I 75% believe this, but I 25% disbelieve it.”

Beliefs are binary. In the typical human experience, we either believe something or we don’t.

We may have different degrees of confidence about our belief, but the belief itself is either there or it isn’t.

 

How Things Work in Science

It is readily admitted by scientists that the results of science are always provisional.

No matter how much evidence has been accumulated for a scientific theory, it’s always possible that new evidence will emerge that indicates the theory must be modified or rejected in favor of a better one.

But that doesn’t stop scientists from believing particular scientific claims.

Based on the evidence so far accumulated, they accept—let’s say—the existence of electrons. They believe in them, and then they proceed about their business on the premise that electrons exist, without doubting this.

If someone asks them how sure they are that electrons exist, they may stop and mentally review the evidence and say something like, “Well, the results of science are always provisional, so I can’t say with infallible certainty that they do. But the evidence is so strong that I can’t imagine a scenario where sufficient evidence would emerge to overturn their existence. So, I believe that electrons do exist, and I don’t worry about the tiny chance that they don’t.”

In saying something like this, a scientist would be acknowledging that:

    1. There is always a gap between the evidence at hand and total certainty, and
    2. That this gap is sufficiently small that the scientist doesn’t worry about it.

In other words, the scientist has made a leap of faith to overcome the evidential gap. He then adopts the belief that electrons exist, and he doesn’t deem it worthwhile to worry about the possibility that he is wrong unless something happens to cause him to reflect on the question.

 

Everyday Life

Such leaps of scientific faith are omnipresent in the sciences, but the same applies in all areas of human life.

For example, most people believe that their spouses are not secretly trying to kill them. The evidence for this proposition is significantly less than the evidence for the existence of electrons.

In fact—among a population of billions—any number of people do try to kill their spouses. But—absent evidence that this is the case in a particular instance—the odds are so low that it is not worth worrying about.

People thus accumulate a certain amount of evidence—e.g., that someone loves them and will not kill them—they adopt the belief, “I am safe with this person,” they marry them, and then they don’t worry about it until significant evidence emerges to the contrary.

This is simply how human belief works.

And so, the idea that we should proportion our belief to the evidence does not describe the human experience.

Instead, we see enough evidence that we deem it rational to adopt a belief, we adopt it, and then we don’t worry about the chance we are wrong until something happens that causes us to question the belief.

In other words, we make a leap of faith to overcome the gap between the evidence we have and the position of belief (i.e., acceptance of a proposition without worrying about it) that we need to achieve in order to move on with life.

 

Paranoia and Self-Interest

We even have a word for people who fail to do this and who continue to worry about the possibility they are wrong: We call them paranoid.

If—despite the evidence a person has that they are safe with their spouse—they continue to worry about the idea that their spouse is going to kill them, that person is paranoid, and we tell them so.

“Look,” we may say, “it is hypothetically possible that your spouse is plotting your murder. But the evidence for that is so small that you shouldn’t be worrying about it. You are only hurting yourself by doing so—and you may be dooming your marriage to failure.”

By making an argument like this, we are appealing to the person’s interests.

They are currently hurting themselves with unnecessary worry—which is contrary to their interests.

And they may in the future hurt the interests of both themselves and their spouse by dooming a marriage that can otherwise benefit both.

In appealing to them to stop worrying, we urge them to use practical reason to overcome the evidential gap between what they’ve seen and the subjective certitude they need to move on with their life on the belief that they are safe with their spouse.

In other words, we are counseling them to make a leap of faith in their own self-interest.

 

Back to Science

This is the same thing every scientist does when they make a leap of scientific faith between the evidence that electrons exist and the belief that they do—or any other scientific belief they may entertain.

At some point, it would become scientific paranoia to continue to have doubts or anxiety about the existence of electrons (or whatever).

We would thus counsel a paranoid scientist to set aside his doubts and move on—given that he lacks compelling evidence to the contrary.

Is it rational—in terms of self-interest—for the scientist to worry about the reality of electrons, or is it better to believe that they do and move on—being willing to reconsider this if contrary evidence emerges in the future?

If the scientist continues to devote time and energy to the non-existence of electrons—in spite of the current evidence—he is hurting himself and his career.

He is harming his quest for greater scientific understanding by wasting time on an exceedingly unlikely hypothesis, and also hurting society at large by denying others the discoveries he could otherwise make.

We thus counsel him to set aside his worries and make the scientific leap of faith needed to overcome the evidential gap between what experiments have shown and belief (acceptance without worry) that electrons exist.

 

Preliminary Lessons

From the preceding, I take it that there is simply a difference between the degree of confidence that the evidence alone would warrant and the belief that corresponds to this.

It is rational to make leaps of faith between the two—and it is rational to do so on practical (prudential) grounds.

At some point, the evidential chance of being wrong is low enough that it simply is not worth worrying about the idea one is wrong.

Instead, it is in one’s interest—and the interests of others—to set aside doubts and proceed on the basis of belief.

At some point, we judge it impractical to continue to worry above the evidential gap and choose to embrace a belief on practical grounds. That’s just how humans work.

I thus take it as established—at least from this point forward—that there is a difference between:

    • Whether we believe a proposition (which is binary; we either believe a proposition or we don’t), and
    • What degree of confidence we feel regarding the proposition when we review the evidence for it.

I further take it as established that:

    • It can be rational to believe a proposition even if the confidence level we feel based on the evidence is less than what would be required for infallible certainty,
    • We all do this constantly; we all wager, all the time, and
    • There is nothing wrong with this; it is how human cognition works.

This puts us in a position to consider interesting aspects of the reasoning involved in Pascal’s Wager.

 

A Limit of Pascal’s Wager

Pascal’s Wager was formulated to help a person in a specific situation—being torn between belief in the Christian God and a western form of skepticism that would involve agnosticism or materialistic atheism. As a result, it does not deal with other religious options.

Many have pointed out that there are other options, and the wager doesn’t address them. This is true, but it does not deprive the wager of its utility for those who are in this situation.

In his 1896 lecture “The Will to Believe” (later published as an essay), William James provided helpful discussion of this subject, noting that—for various people—some hypotheses are “live” while others are “dead.”

James defined a live hypothesis as “one which appeals as a real possibility to him to whom it is proposed,” whereas a dead hypothesis is one that does not strike the hearer as a real possibility.

James referred to the decision between two hypotheses as an “option” and stated:

A living option is one in which both hypotheses are live ones.

If I say to you: “Be a theosophist or be a Mohammedan,” it is probably a dead option, because for you neither hypothesis is likely to be alive.

But if I say: “Be an agnostic or be Christian,” it is otherwise: trained as you are, each hypothesis makes some appeal, however small, to your belief.

Pascal’s Wager, then, is designed to help a person for whom both Christianity and western skepticism are live hypotheses.

 

Other Wagers

However, wager-style reasoning can be applied to other situations. To cite a simple example that I’ve discussed before, one can construct a kind of “reincarnation wager.”

Suppose a person’s live option is whether to believe in reincarnation or whether to believe that this life is the only one we have.

How we spend our time has consequences—whether it is achieving goals with respect to this life or with respect to the afterlife.

Consequently, if a person feels unable to decide the issue of reincarnation based on evidence, it will be in his interest to believe the latter so as to make the most of the time he has. If it turns out he is wrong and he reincarnates, he will simply get more time to pursue his goals and “get it right.”

There also can be a similar “afterlife wager” for those who have a live option between believing that there is no afterlife and the possibility that there is an afterlife in which we experience positive or negative consequences based on what we do in this one.

If one is unable to decide this question based on evidence, it will be prudent to assume that there is such an afterlife so as to take reasonable steps to ensure a good afterlife.

If it turned out that the person were wrong and there was no afterlife, the person would not experience a negative one and would only have wasted reasonable efforts in pursuit of a good one.

 

Wagering, Materialism, and Morals

In light of the applicability of wager-style arguments to other situations, I’d like to address one involving materialism and morals.

Despite the fact we all constantly wager and adopt beliefs based partly on practical rather than evidential reasons, one of the concerns limiting the use of wager-like reasoning is a nagging anxiety people have about whether they are doing something “wrong” by adopting beliefs on these grounds.

I concede that people have a moral intuition that there needs to be some kind of relationship between belief and evidence.

For example, we have the intuition that we would be violating what philosophers call our “epistemic duties” if we chose to believe something that had a massive amount of evidence against it and no evidence for it.

This is true. However, it is not applicable to the situation that Pascal’s Wager is designed to address.

The wager is specifically intended to address a situation in which a person has considered the evidence and still feels unable to make an evidence-based decision.

Further, as William James points out, we may be forced to make a choice, for to refuse to adopt belief in a proposition is to adopt the alternative of non-belief in it. James discusses this in terms of a decision between adopting a religious view or not doing so:

[W]e see, first that religion offers itself as a momentous option. We are supposed to gain, even now, by our belief, and to lose by our nonbelief, a certain vital good.

Secondly, religion is a forced option, so far as that good goes. We cannot escape the issue by remaining sceptical and waiting for more light, because, although we do avoid error in that way if religion be untrue, we lose the good, if it be true, just as certainly as if we positively chose to disbelieve.

It is as if a man should hesitate indefinitely to ask a certain woman to marry him because he was not perfectly sure that she would prove an angel after he brought her home. Would he not cut himself off from that particular angel-possibility as decisively as if he went and married some one else?

Scepticism, then, is not avoidance of option; it is option of a certain particular kind of risk. Better risk loss of truth than chance of error—that is your faith-vetoer’s exact position. He is actively playing his stake as much as the believer is; he is backing the field against the religious hypothesis, just as the believer is backing the religious hypothesis against the field.

One thus does not escape the trap of making a choice in this situation. It is simply a choice between belief and non-belief.

And—in the absence of evidence that decides the matter—it is made on non-evidential grounds no matter which choice is made.

 

Religion vs. Scientific Materialism

The above illustrates the difficulties with the idea that it is somehow immoral—a violation of epistemic duties—to adopt a belief based partly on pragmatic rather than evidential concerns.

However, there is more that can be said about this when a particular situation is considered—that is, one like Pascal’s original situation of a person torn between Christianity and skepticism.

Today in the West, skepticism typically entails a form of materialism in which science is given a primary place (i.e., scientific materialism).

Conventional science is driven by empirical phenomena—things that can be observed and measured using the conventional senses (sight, hearing, etc.) and their technological extensions (microscopes, telescopes, spectrometers, gas chromatographs, etc.).

Science is held to be incapable of investigating non-empirical phenomena (souls, spirits, God), and so these are deemed outside the realm of science.

Indeed, for scientific materialism, it is the non-empirical quality of these entities that drives rejection of their existence in the first place.

However, it isn’t only souls, spirits, and God that are not subject to empirical investigation. It is also morality.

Moral properties like good and evil, right and wrong, cannot be detected with the senses or their technological extensions. As a result, it is difficult to see how morality could be real if scientific materialism were true.

 

Another Wager

This leads us to another wager—this time between a religious worldview and scientific materialism:

1) Suppose a person adopts a religious worldview, and it turned out that scientific materialism were right and that there are no non-empirical things.

In that case, the person would not be violating their epistemic duties because morality would be a fiction, and the person had done nothing wrong by being religious.

2) On the other hand, suppose that a person adopts a worldview of scientific materialism, and it turns out the religious worldview is correct.

On the religious worldview, morality is real, and one should be a moral person. The person then has a choice:

a) In keeping with their scientific materialism, they could reject the real existence on the grounds that it is non-empirical. In this case, they would be doing something wrong because the religious worldview is true and morality is real.

b) Or, despite their scientific materialism, they could continue to accept the real existence of morality. In this case they also would be doing something wrong, because they are violating their own principles, and violating your own principles is morally wrong.

We thus see that (1) if a person incorrectly adopts a religious viewpoint, he does nothing wrong, while (2) if he incorrectly adopts scientific materialism, he inescapably does something wrong.

Given these facts, the logical thing to do is to accept the religious worldview since—whether it is correct or not—one avoids doing something wrong.

 

Testing the Wager

One way of testing this wager is to ask, “If the religious worldview is true, could I still be doing something wrong by adopting it? Not in the sense of being religious, because we’re assuming this view is true. But perhaps by violating my epistemic duties in some way from within a religious perspective?”

At this point, we are speaking purely from within a religious perspective. We are taking it that religion is true and asking whether one can violate one’s epistemic duties and thus do something morally wrong.

The answer, of course, is yes. From a religious perspective, people of any stripe—religious or not—need to be moral people, and that includes honoring their epistemic duties.

If a person—religious or non-religious—stifles his conscience to convince himself that murder is an okay thing to do, then he is violating his epistemic duties.

So, yes, religious people can violate their epistemic duties. But what does this have to do with the question of being religious itself?

We can infer from this that one should not violate one’s epistemic duties by adopting beliefs that one should not, so don’t join a religion that teaches them.

If you have a functioning conscience, don’t become a member of the Manson Family and participate in its murder sprees. And if you have good evidence that evolution is true, don’t join a church that insists on Young Earth Creationism.

 

The Religious View in General

But how would one be violating one’s religious duties merely by adopting a religious point of view?

This returns us to the question of evidence and what relationship it has with belief adoption.

If a person thought that he had conclusive evidence against religion, then he should not adopt a religious point of view.

And if a person thought he had conclusive evidence for religion, then he should adopt it.

However, neither of these situations is what wager-style arguments are designed to address (or at least the kind that we are considering). They are for people who don’t think that they can settle the matter based on their review of the evidence.

But there is still a need to settle it, and so wagers appeal to practical reason to overcome the evidential gap—just as we do in science and in everyday life.

Given the omnipresence of pragmatic leaps of faith in every field of human endeavor—indeed, in virtually every belief we adopt except as the result of a mathematical demonstration—it is hard to see how using practical reason to overcome an evidential deadlock could be seen as violating our epistemic duties.

We use practical reason to overcome evidential gaps all the time. It is built into human nature, and so we are simply acting in accord with our nature when we do so. There is nothing wrong with this.

 

Intellectual and Moral Coherence

Further, adopting a religious perspective provides a greater degree of intellectual and moral coherence than adopting scientific materialism.

Whether or not one is religious, we have an inbuilt moral sense that tells us that we have moral duties, including the epistemic ones that the person torn between religion and materialism is concerned about.

On a materialist view, these may have an evolutionary explanation, but they do not objectively bind, and—as non-empirical—they should not be given credence.

Nevertheless—unless they are psychopaths—materialists find themselves inescapably falling back into thinking and acting as if morality is objectively real. They are as horrified by murder, bigotry, and oppression as anyone—even though their worldview would imply that there is nothing objectively wrong with any of these.

Materialists thus have a lived experience that is inconsistent with their belief system, resulting in a lack of coherence between the two.

By contrast, on the religious view, non-empirical entities are real, and this provides an intellectual framework that allows our in-built moral sense to be what we take it to be—a reflection of reality and something that is objectively binding on us.

The religious view thus provides a form of coherence between the intellectual and the moral that scientific materialism does not.

Coherence between belief and lived experience is a desirable feature of worldviews, and the religious worldview offers this regarding moral realism, whereas materialism does not.

This is one more reason—in addition to the evidential and pragmatic reasons—to prefer the religious worldview.

Can the Soul Be Weighed?

NOTE: I submitted the following as a term paper for the course “Skeptical Approach to Parapsychology” at the Rhine Education Center.

The assignment was to take a noteworthy parapsychological study and evaluate it by apply critical thinking–being neither unduly credulous nor unduly dismissive of its claims.

(Also, since the assignment was to approach the task from a scientific, parapsychological perspective rather than a religious one, I don’t simply provide a theological analysis of what the soul is, and I consider options a non-religious researcher would need to.)

The paper received an “A.”

 

Can the Soul Be Weighed?

by Jimmy Akin

A minor pop culture trope holds the human soul weighs about as much as a piece of bread, or 21 grams. This trope appears various places, including the title of the 2003 Sean Penn movie 21 Grams.

The trope’s basis is a set of experiments begun in 1901 by Duncan MacDougall, M.D. His results were published in 1907 in American Medicine and the Journal of the American Society for Psychical Research (vol. 1, no. 5).

MacDougall weighed humans and dogs at the moment of death and—in the case of humans—found a measurable loss of weight coincident with death. After accounting for known, natural substances the subjects’ bodies could have released, MacDougall conjectured the loss of weight may have been due to the departing human soul.

 

Rationale for Experiment

MacDougall explains the basis for his experiment by stating that, if the personality survives death, it must exist as a “space occupying body.” He writes:

It is unthinkable that personality and consciousness continuing personal identity should exist, and have being, and yet not occupy space. It is impossible to represent in thought that which is not space occupying, as having personality, for that would be equivalent to thinking that nothing had become or was something, that emptiness had personality, that space itself was more than space, all of which are contradictions and absurd.

He reasons that whatever substance this personality-bearing, “space occupying body” (hereafter “soul,” for convenience) may have a measurable weight. He writes:

According to the latest conception of science, substance or space occupying material is divisible into that which is gravitative—solids, liquids, gasses, all having weight—and the ether which is non-gravitative.

MacDougall considers whether the soul might be made of normal “gravitative” matter, although he also considers two alternatives.

The first is that the soul might be made of luminiferous ether—a substance formerly believed to fill the universe and be responsible for propagating light waves through space. MacDougall thinks this option impossible, since ether was believed to be continuous throughout the universe, whereas individuals’ personalities are separate and distinct.

The second alternative is that the soul may be made of “a middle form of substance neither gravitative matter nor ether, not capable of being weighed, and yet not identical with ether.” Such a “middle form” might be non-continuous, allowing separate personalities/souls, but still not being weighable. However, MacDougall thinks it more reasonable to suppose that the soul “must be some form of gravitative matter” since it is linked organically with the body until death.

He thus proposes weighing dying individuals.

 

Examining the Rationale

MacDougall’s rationale is clever and worth examining in light of the history of philosophy and subsequent scientific developments.

Although he says it is “unthinkable” that the soul is not a space-filling body, many prior thinkers disagreed. In the Middle Ages, it was a commonplace for philosophers to regard spirits—including God, angels, and human souls—as entities that lacked extension in space. These spirits could be said to be “in a place” in an accommodated sense. When a spirit manifested its influence on something in the material world, the spirit could be said to be “in” that location (cf. Summa Theologiae I:52:1).

In the Early Modern period, there was renewed discussion of this subject, with Renee Descartes taking the position that the soul is non-extended and Henry More arguing that spirits must be extended. (An issue that arose as a result of this discussion was how a non-extended, immaterial entity could control a body since the two could not have physical contact. Parapsychologically, this would be “explained” in terms of psychokinesis [PK], though the basis or bases of PK remain very unclear.)

Since many thinkers consider the idea of a non-extended soul conceivable, we will include this possibility when considering MacDougall’s results.

From a scientific perspective, MacDougall’s discussion of ether has been superseded. Evidence against the existence of ether had been discovered in the famous, 1887 Michelson-Morley experiment, and the idea ceased to be commonly used in physics during the twentieth century.

However, something like MacDougall’s “middle form” of matter/energy emerged in twentieth century science—that is, things other than ether that lack mass. Current science holds that there are massless particles, such as the photon and gluon. However, these are force-carrying particles and are not thought to form structures that would be capable of sustaining a personality independent of massive particles.

A possibility MacDougall didn’t consider was that the soul might be made of a gravitative substance different than the solid, liquid, or gaseous states known in his day. While subsequent science has proposed additional states of matter, such as Bose-Einstein condensates, none of these are good candidates for the soul. (E.g., Bose-Einstein condensates can exist only close to absolute zero, and it would seem impossible for such a substance to coexist with a warm, living human body.)

In light of parapsychological research suggesting that ghosts are not electromagnetic phenomena, an interesting thought that could not have occurred to MacDougall would be the idea that souls might be made of “dark matter”—a hypothetical form of matter that does not interact with the electromagnetic force but that does interact gravitationally. The loss of such a soul could be weighable, and yet the soul would not show up on EMF detectors. (It should be immediately pointed out that current dark matter theories do not predict the existence of soul-like objects, but neither do they completely rule them out. A dark matter soul would need to interact with its body through a form of PK rather than EM.)

 

MacDougall’s Experiments

The design MacDougall used for his experiments was carefully thought out.

For human subjects, he arranged a large platform scale on which a bed could be set, along with a dying patient, and then balanced it. The scale was sensitive to two tenths of an ounce (5.7 grams).

With patient consent, MacDougall chose subjects dying of conditions expected to result in a peaceful passing so as not to jar the scale with death throes. (All died of tuberculosis—“consumption”—except for one in a diabetic coma.)

He tracked the subjects’ weight in the hours preceding death to account for the natural loss of moisture that occurs through perspiration and respiration when the body is not being hydrated.

He then recorded any sudden change the scale registered at the time of death—to the extent this could be determined in his day. (Since electrocardiogram [ECG] monitoring was still being pioneered, this involved observing signs such as cessation of eye and muscle movement, breathing, and heartbeat—as determined by stethoscope.)

After death, MacDougall checked if the subject’s bowels had moved and whether—and how much—urine had been discharged.

For his canine subjects, MacDougall was unable to find dogs dying in peaceful ways. He thus used healthy dogs, sedated them to keep them still, and euthanized them—while monitoring their weight on scales that were sensitive to 1/16th of an ounce (1.8 grams).

 

MacDougall’s Results

Six trials were done with human subjects, with the following results (all numbers converted to metric):


Subject
Measurement at Death Second, Later Measurement
1 -21 g
2 -14 g -46 g
3 -14 g -43 g
4* -11 to -14 g
5 -11 g
6* -43 g

The measurements at death represent sudden drops that occurred within the space of “a few seconds.”

In two cases, a second measurement was taken shortly after death:

    • Subject 2’s initial measurement was a sudden loss coincident with the last movement of the facial muscles, and the second reading was taken after cessation of heartbeat was verified.
    • Subject 3’s additional reading was taken “a few minutes” after death.

MacDougall eliminated the results of Subjects 4 and 6 (marked by asterisks) from consideration:

    • With Subject 4, MacDougall reports that “unfortunately our scales were not finely adjusted and there was a good deal of interference by people opposed to our work”—apparently hospital employees who regarded the experiment as too morbid. However, “at death the beam sunk so that it required from three-eighths to one-half ounce to bring it back to the point preceding death.”
    • With Subject 6, although MacDougall recorded the measurement at death, he rejected it since “the patient died almost within five minutes after being placed upon the bed and died while I was adjusting the beam.”

Fifteen trials were conducted with canine subjects. MacDougall reports:

The same experiments were carried out on fifteen dogs, surrounded by every precaution to obtain accuracy and the results were uniformly negative, no loss of weight at death.

 

Eliminating Naturalistic Explanations

MacDougall sought to account for conventional material substances released by the body—moisture in the form of respiration and perspiration, as well as evaporation from urine and feces.

He tracked a slow, steady loss of weight before death due to moisture loss through respiration and perspiration, so this could not be responsible for the sudden drops coincident with the moment of death.

His subjects did not suddenly expel 11-21 grams of moisture with their last breaths. Neither did they suddenly release this amount of perspiration, which would have remained in contact with their bodies and the bedclothes and only evaporate slowly, meaning it still would have been weighed by the scale.

MacDougall did not report the subjects experiencing bowel movements upon death, though if they had, the feces “would still have remained upon the bed except for a slow loss by the evaporation of moisture depending of course, upon the fluidity of the feces.”

He reported some subjects releasing urine upon death (due to the relaxation of the urinary sphincter), however, “the urine remained upon the bed and could not have evaporated enough through the thick bed clothing to have influenced the result.”

Having eliminated semi-solid and liquid substances released by the body, MacDougall sought to account for gas that could be suddenly released at death—i.e., air in the lungs.

Physics indicates this should not matter. At ground level, the Earth’s atmosphere is pressing downward on objects, including the scale, and it does not matter whether the air is in the subject’s lungs or above the chest. The scale should not be materially affected, which is what MacDougall found:

Getting upon the bed myself, my colleague put the beam at actual balance. Inspiration and expiration of air as forcibly as possible by me had no effect upon the beam. My colleague got upon the bed, and I placed the beam at balance. Forcible inspiration and expiration of air on his part had no effect.

 

Alternative Naturalistic Explanations

Alternative explanations for MacDougall’s results have been proposed. A selection is considered and critiqued by Masayoshi Ishida in the Journal of Scientific Exploration (vol. 24, no. 1), though what follows here are principally my own thoughts.

Since the human body begins to cool at death, could the loss of heat be responsible for the observed loss in weight—either directly or due to a change in air currents (as proposed by Len Fisher)?

Neither would be plausible. Heat is produced by the small-scale motion of atoms, and the fact these vibrate less after death does not change their weight. Only a large-scale removal of atoms from the bed would produce the observed readings.

Similarly, while convection currents caused by the heat of a living body might lightly press down on the bed—if such currents existed in these cases—they would not dissipate at the moment of death. The coldness of death—known as algor mortis—takes hours to occur and is frequently used to determine time of death in criminal investigations. There would be no sudden loss of weight.

What about heartbeat or breathing? These produce vibrations that could affect a scale, and they cease suddenly at death. However, they would cause a living, prone patient to slightly oscillate up and down on the bed, and if the scale were visibly at balance when the patient was alive then it should remain even more steadily (and likely sub-perceptually) at balance upon death. There would not be a sudden drop of 11-21 grams.

It could be proposed that there was something wrong with MacDougall’s scales, that the measurements he took were botched, or that he committed fraud. However, there does not appear to be evidence supporting these hypotheses.

 

Paranormal Speculations

Lacking a good naturalistic explanation for MacDougall’s results, it is reasonable to consider paranormal explanations. These can only be speculative due to the limited data his experiment returned. Replication and new types of experiments would be needed to test individual hypotheses.

The first possibility is MacDougall’s own conjecture—that the loss of weight may be due to the departure of the soul, conceived of as a space-filling entity capable of being weighed.

If so, the soul might be a very fine structure made of conventional matter/energy recognized by the Standard Model of particle physics. Alternately, it might be made of an undiscovered form of matter that interacts gravitationally.

Questions that might be asked are what would account for the variance in numbers MacDougall saw upon death, what was responsible for the additional weight loss in the second readings, and why there was no weight loss observed with dogs.

All the readings were within a factor of ~4 (11-46g), and the readings at the moment of death were within a factor of 2 (11-21g). Given the small sample size (4-6, depending on which are counted) and the sensitivity threshold of the scale (5.7 grams), these differences might simply be due to normal variation in taking measurements.

However, it also is possible that—just as some humans have heavier bodies—some humans have heavier souls.

If further experiments showed that the second, greater readings taken in two cases represent a real, second post-mortem weight loss, it might be proposed that there is more than one paranormal “thing” that detaches at death.

This idea may correspond to certain religious conceptions. In ancient Egypt, the human was thought to consist not only of the physical body but also several soul-like entities referred to as the ba, the ka, the shut, etc. Similarly, some Christians have understood humans as being tripartite, consisting of body, soul, and spirit. Even body/spirit dualists like John Duns Scotus have held that humans have multiple intangible “substantial forms” when alive.

Such claims, in light of MacDougall’s second readings, should alert us to the possibility that the death process may involve more than the departure of a single soul-like entity.

When it comes to dogs, MacDougall’s results would be equally consistent with the hypotheses that dogs do not have souls that survive death or that their souls produce results below the sensitivity threshold of the scale used (1.8g).

Attention should be paid to how MacDougall’s results might be explained if the soul is not spatially extended, as various philosophers have proposed. Why would the departure of such an entity result in an observed loss of weight?

It seems difficult to imagine a non-extended entity having intrinsic mass, but the soul could still interact with weighable matter. This would seem to be a form of PK, and two possibilities for the loss of weight spring to mind.

First, the soul would seem to have a tight psychokinetic association with the body during life, as illustrated by the ease of producing voluntary motions (e.g., lifting an arm) and the difficulty in psychokinetically moving objects outside the body. This tight association might not instantaneously vanish upon death. The soul might retain a PK “grip” on particles or atoms within the body, and as the soul detaches during the death process, enough of these might be pulled along with it to explain the loss of weight.

Second, there may be an explanation in line with the super-psi hypothesis that psychic functioning is part of people’s activity in their everyday environments. People use their bodies to steady themselves as they navigate their surroundings, resulting in them shifting their weight as they move body parts. They might use PK to assist this process. They might even continuously, psychokinetically cause their bodies to slightly sink down as part of steadying themselves in their environment, and if this PK ceased upon the departure of the soul, it could result in the observed loss of a number of grams.

In both this and the previous case, MacDougall’s variant readings might be explained by differences in the strength of the subjects’ PK. Depending on how the death process works from the soul’s perspective, it might also explain the larger, apparently postmortem readings he obtained in two cases—as the soul detached or the PK ceased functioning in stages.

 

Conclusion

MacDougall’s 1907 paper remains intriguing, and a good naturalistic explanation for his results has not been found.

Unfortunately, the small sample size he was able to achieve greatly limits the paper’s evidential value. MacDougall wanted to perform many more experiments with human subjects, but opposition to the project made this impossible.

Thus far, it appears no one has attempted to replicate his experiment with dying humans. However, there have been attempts to do so with animals. In 1907 the Los Angeles Herald reported on an animal replication effort by H. La Verne Twining, which produced mixed results.

Unfortunately, until human replications are attempted with substantially larger sample sizes—as well as modern measurement and control methods—MacDougall’s paper remains only a fascinating, suggestive study.

Checking Out of Hilbert’s Hotel (Kalam Cosmological Argument)

In Reasonable Faith, William Lane Craig seeks to show the absurdity of an actually infinity of things by appealing to surprises that await us at Hilbert’s Grand Hotel.

This is a thought experiment proposed by the German mathematician David Hilbert (1862-1943). In the thought experiment, Hilbert envisioned a Grand Hotel with an infinite number of rooms, all of which are full.

Hilbert then posed a series of scenarios that would allow the hotel to accept additional guests—both any finite number of guests, and even an infinite number of guests!

Craig poses four scenarios involving Hilbert’s Hotel, which I will summarize this way:

    1. A Single New Guest: The hotel is full and a new guest arrives. The manager has each current guest move to the next higher room, freeing up the first room for the new arrival.
    2. Infinite New Guests: The hotel is full and an infinite number of new guests arrive. The manager has each current guest move to the room whose number is double that of their current room. This puts all the existing guests in the even numbered rooms, leaving the odd numbered rooms free to accept the infinite number of new arrivals.
    3. Odd Numbers Check Out: The hotel is full and all the odd numbered guests decide to check out, leaving their rooms vacant. The manager then has the guests in the even numbered rooms move to the room whose number is half that of their current room. This fills up both the odd and the even numbered rooms, and the hotel is completely full again.
    4. Guests Above 3 Check Out: The hotel is full and all of the guests with room numbers above 3 check out, leaving only three guests in the hotel. Yet since the set {4, 5, 6, . . . } has the same “size” as the set {1, 3, 5 . . . }, it would seem that the same number of guests checked out in this example as in the previous one, but the resulting number of guests in the hotel was different.

Craig regards all of these as absurd and concludes both that such a hotel could not exist and that an actual infinity of things cannot exist.

How might we respond to this?

 

Yes, They’re Strange

My first response would be to say, “Yes, these are strange, surprising, and counter-intuitive. If you want, you can even call them absurd.”

But that’s not what I’m interested in. There are lots of true things that fit those descriptions.

What I’m concerned with is whether any of these situations entail logical contradictions that God could not actualize in some possible world, and it’s not obvious that they do.

 

What Infinity Means

It seems to me that part of the problem is that we have a persistent tendency to slip into thinking of infinity as if it is a particular, concrete, limited number. It’s not. By definition, it is unlimited. That’s what the term “infinite” means. But as long as we use labels like “infinity,” we tend to slip into thinking of this as if it were an ordinary, limited number rather than something of unlimited magnitude.

It can help to strip away the label and repose the question without it.

    • Suppose that I had an unlimited number of apples. Then you bring me a new apple, and I add it to my collection. How many apples do I have now? Well, it’s still an unlimited number. Adding a new item to an already unlimited collection isn’t going to change the status of the collection from unlimited to limited, so it’s still unlimited.
    • Suppose that you bring me a whole bunch of apples—an unlimited number of them—and I dump them into my collection. How many are there now? Again, adding even an unlimited number of apples to my already unlimited collection won’t change the status of my collection from unlimited to limited, so it’s still unlimited.
    • Suppose that you go through my apple collection and pull out all the odd numbered apples (let’s suppose that I’ve conveniently numbered them so I can always find the apple I want). How many are left in the collection? Pulling out every other apple from an unlimited number of apples would still leave an unlimited number there, so my collection is still of unlimited size. And I can re-number the apples I have left if I want.
    • Finally, suppose that you pull all of the apples out of my collection except the first three. How many do I have left? Three. “Why is the number different than when I pulled out the odd numbered ones?” you might ask. “Because of which ones you pulled out,” I reply. “The first time, you pulled out every other apple, but the second time you pulled out all of the apples but the first three. Of course, you’re going to get a different number left over at the end.”

What we’ve just done here is run through the same scenarios that Craig uses, only we’ve done it with apples instead of hotel rooms and we’ve done it using the intuitive term “unlimited” rather than less intuitive terms like “infinity” or “aleph-null,” both of which suggest a definite amount to our ears.

When we keep the fact that the amount is unlimited clearly in focus, the situation sounds quite a bit less counter-intuitive. The reason is that we aren’t losing sight of the not-limited amounts we are playing with.

 

But Could All This Really Exist?

Certainly not in our universe—not without God suspending the physical laws he has set up to govern it.

If a hotelier decided to build a hotel with an infinite number of rooms, he would be immediately confronted with the fact that there isn’t enough room on earth to house such a hotel, there aren’t enough construction workers to build it, and he doesn’t have an infinite amount of money.

Similarly, I can’t go to a store, or an orchard, or any number of stores and orchards, and buy an infinite number of apples. (Nor do I have an infinite amount of money—quite the opposite, in fact!)

So, both the hotelier and I would quickly discover that our projects are practically impossible (meaning: not possible given the practical restrictions we operate under).

Yet suppose the hotelier and I were to make go of our projects, somehow pulling in resources from off-world once earth’s supplies started to go low. At some point the hotel and the apple collection would collapse under their own mass.

If we kept loading material into them, they would become so massive that they would begin to fuse, and they would both turn into stars.

If we still kept loading material into them, they would become more massive yet and, eventually, millions of years later, go supernova and turn into black holes.

Such is the way of things, given the physical laws that operate in our universe.

Even if God were to intervene and miraculously allow the things to be built and not become black holes, we still wouldn’t be able to do the infinite amount of guest and apple shuffling involved in the thought experiments. We wouldn’t have the time!

So, I’m quite prepared to concede that, in addition to being practically impossible, the infinite hotel and the infinite apple collection are also physically impossible (meaning: not possible given the physical laws of our universe).

But that’s not our question. We’re not asking about practical possibility or even physical possibility. We’re asking about logical possibility.

 

How useful is a hotel metaphor?

Here I would like to introduce what I think is the main problem with Craig’s use of Hilbert’s Hotel to disprove the possibility of an infinite history: I just don’t think it’s relevant.

Even if you grant that Hilbert’s Hotel involves a logical impossibility, that doesn’t show that all actual infinities involve a logical impossibility.

We’ve already shown that there is an actually infinite set of mathematical truths, so that is logically possible.

And that actual infinity does not seem to be subject to the same kind of difficulties that Hilbert’s Hotel raises. Even if we were to start numbering the different mathematical truths the way the rooms in Hilbert’s Hotel are numbered, we couldn’t perform the kind of manipulations on them that the hotelier does.

We couldn’t have the mathematical truths move around the way the guests in the hotel do. We couldn’t make new mathematical truths appear or existing mathematical truths vanish.

We could change the numbers we apply to these truths, but that’s not the same thing. That’s just our labeling. It doesn’t affect the truths themselves.

The apple collection fares no better. We can’t move, add, or delete mathematical truths the way we can apples. Mathematical truths are just there.

And so it seems that the kind of puzzles we can generate with Hilbert’s Hotel simply do not arise with the actual infinity of mathematical truths.

This means, if we grant that Hilbert’s Hotel involves a logical contradiction, that we have to ask the question: How relevant is it to the idea of God creating an infinite history for the universe? Is the idea of an infinite history in the same category as Hilbert’s Hotel or in the same category as the set of mathematical truths?

 

Some Similarities

At first glance, you might think that an infinite history would go in the same category as Hilbert’s Hotel.

For one thing, Hilbert’s Hotel involves an infinite amount of space (the infinite rooms it contains), and an infinite history would involve an infinite amount of time. We could map the rooms of Hilbert’s Hotel onto the individual moments of time in the universe’s history.

Furthermore, the rooms in Hilbert’s Hotel have content (guests and the things they are doing in their rooms), and the moments of history have content (people and the things they are doing—or at least whatever God would have chosen to put in them).

But these similarities turn out to be rather superficial. In fact, you could map any countably infinite set onto any other countably infinite set. You could, thus, map the rooms of Hilbert’s Hotel onto something totally non-physical, like the mathematical truths that fit the form X + 1 = Y, like this:

    • Room 1 –> (1 + 1 = 2)
    • Room 2 –> (2 + 1 = 3)
    • Room 3 –> (3 + 1 = 4)
    • Room 4 –> (4 + 1 = 5)

And just as each room in the hotel has contents (guests), each slot in our sequence of mathematical truths has contents (the particular truth in question).

The real issue is whether the moments of history and their contents can be manipulated the way that the rooms and guests in a hotel can.

And they can’t be.

 

Time Can Be Rewritten?

Despite Doctor Who’s repeated assurances that time can be rewritten, this question has proved a real puzzler for philosophers and scientists.

Scientists are of different opinions about whether time travel to the past is physically possible. Einstein was startled when, in honor of his 70th birthday, Kurt Gödel gave him a proof showing that Einstein’s own equations would allow for the possibility of time travel if we are living in a certain kind of universe.[1]

So what would happen if you really were able to go back in time? Could you change history? Could you carry out the famous “grandfather paradox,” where you kill your own grandfather before the conception of your father, thus preventing your own birth? (And, by extension, preventing you from coming back in time to kill your grandfather.)

According to much of the thinking on the issue, there would be two possibilities:

1) You simply would not be able to kill your grandfather. According to this view, time has an as-yet undiscovered principle that prevents time paradoxes from happening. This was proposed in the 1980s by the Russian physicist Igor Novikov (b. 1935), and the proposed principle is known as the Novikov self-consistency principle.

2) You would be able to kill your grandfather, but in so doing you would create a new timeline. According to this view, you would be able to kill your grandfather, but this would not change your history. The timeline in which your father and you were born would still exist. That timeline has to still exist, because you need to leave at some point to come back in the past. What would happen if you kill your grandfather is you would cause a new timeline to branch off from the original one, and in the new timeline you would never be born. You would still be around, however, because your original timeline is still out there, undamaged.

If the first of these possibilities is correct then the Doctor is simply wrong. Time can’t be rewritten.

If the second of these possibilities is correct then the Doctor is right. –ish. Up to a point.

You could “change history” in the sense of causing a new timeline to branch, one in which you are never born. But you didn’t change your history. The timeline where you were born, grew up, and travelled back in time is still out there. It’s still real. It didn’t un-happen from an external perspective looking at the timelines.

How does this help us answer our question about an infinite history?

 

Forward, into the Past!

The ancients really don’t get enough credit, because since at least the time of the Greeks, people have been asking whether God could change the past.

The poet Agathon (c. 480-440 B.C.) wrote that:

For this alone is lacking even to God,
To make undone things that have once been done.

This statement is quoted and endorsed by Aristotle (Nichomachean Ethics 6:2).

The same view is taken up and endorsed by St. Augustine (c. 354-430), who wrote:

Accordingly, to say, if God is almighty, let Him make what has been done to be undone, is in fact to say, if God is almighty, let Him make a thing to be in the same sense both true and false [Reply to Faustus the Manichean 26:5].

And the same view is endorsed by St. Thomas Aquinas, who wrote:

[T]here does not fall under the scope of God’s omnipotence anything that implies a contradiction. Now that the past should not have been implies a contradiction. For as it implies a contradiction to say that Socrates is sitting, and is not sitting, so does it to say that he sat, and did not sit. But to say that he did sit is to say that it happened in the past. To say that he did not sit, is to say that it did not happen. Whence, that the past should not have been, does not come under the scope of divine power [Summa Theologiae I:25:4].

Notice that both Augustine and Aquinas identify the same reason for God not being able to change the past: It involves a logical contradiction.

Does it?

 

From Here to Eternity

The view that I’ve advocated in this paper—that God is outside of time and that, consequently, the B-Theory of time is true—indicates that God cannot change the past—at least not in the way relevant to our discussion.

To illustrate this, let’s think about a particular moment in my own past, which I have already referred to: the moment when I was five years old and, in my grandmother’s kitchen, reached for a broom, causing a Coke bottle to explode and injure my knee.

That moment is present to God in eternity.

In the eternal now, he is creating that moment in history, and, by my free will, I am grabbing the broom and causing the Coke bottle to explode.

Could God change history so that this doesn’t happen? Could he, for example, give my grandmother a sudden inspiration a few moments earlier so that she can intervene and prevent me from grabbing the broom?

No.

Why not?

Because that moment is present to him in the eternal now. It’s real. He can’t undo it, because there is no time where he is. He can’t first let it happen and then undo it. That would imply the passage of time for God. It would imply more than one moment in the eternal now, in which case God would not be in eternity but in time.

What God could do (I assume) is create a second timeline,[2] in which my grandmother does stop me from breaking the Coke bottle, but that would leave intact the original moment in which I did break it. That moment is still there, still present to God in eternity, and thus still real.

If Akin is right about this then so were Agathon, Aristotle, Augustine, and Aquinas: God cannot undo history.

Once an event has happened in time, it’s set in eternity.

This has important implications for the question of whether he could make an infinite history.

 

Not Like Hilbert’s Hotel

If God can’t change history then time is not like Hilbert’s Hotel.

God cannot, in the eternal now, cut up, rearrange, and reshuffle the moments of history the way Hilbert’s hotelier moved guests around. If Moment 2 follows Moment 1 in time, then that is the way they are arranged before God in eternity. He can’t swap their order because in eternity there is no time for him to swap them in.

God cannot, in the eternal now, create or delete additional moments in time beyond those he has already created, the way I could add or subtract apples from my collection.

There is no time in which God could do these things, because that is the way eternity works by definition. It is thus logically impossible.

That means that the kind of puzzles that arise with Hilbert’s Hotel simply do not arise with time from God’s perspective.

An actually infinite history for the universe thus would go in the same category as an actually infinite number of mathematical truths. It does not give rise to Hilbert paradoxes.

Neither does an actually infinite future for the universe, which is why God is able to create one of those—as he has.

Therefore, even if one grants that Hilbert’s Hotel involves a logical contradiction and could not be realized by an omnipotent God, it does not matter. Viewed from the eternal perspective, an infinite amount of time (past or future) does not generate the problems of Hilbert’s Hotel and so is not in the same category.

 

[1] This solution is known as the “Gödel metric.” For a good popular introduction to the subject of time travel from the perspective of contemporary physics, see The Physics of the Impossible by Michio Kaku, who is a professor of theoretical physics at City University of New York.

[2] Because God is in eternity, this second timeline, and any others he might create, would all exist simultaneously for him in the eternal now, just as our timeline does. From the eternal now, he would be simultaneously creating all of the histories that exist.

 

Catholic Teaching and the Kalaam Argument

While the Catholic Church holds that it is possible to prove the existence of God, it does not have teachings on specific versions of arguments for God’s existence and whether or not they work.

As a result, it does not have a teaching on the Kalaam cosmological argument, and Catholics are free to use it or not, depending on whether they think it works.

 

Catholic Liberty

Historically, major Catholic thinkers have taken different positions on the issue. St. Bonaventure (1221-1274) thought that the argument is successful, while his contemporary St. Thomas Aquinas (1225-1274) famously thought that it does not.

Both of these men have been declared doctors of the Church, meaning that they are among the best, most highly honored theologians.

A key premise of the Kalaam argument is that the universe has a beginning, which is certainly true. The question is how we can show this to a person who doesn’t already believe it.

Back in the 1200s, modern science had not yet been developed, and this premise had to be defended on purely philosophical grounds. On that score, I think St. Thomas Aquinas was right, and the philosophical arguments that have been proposed to show that the universe must have a finite history do not work.

However, in the 20th century the Big Bang was discovered, and current cosmology is consistent with the idea of the universe having a beginning. As a result, I think a properly qualified version of the Kalaam argument can be used, based on modern science.

 

Catholic Limits

While Catholic teaching allows great liberty when it comes to apologetic arguments, there are limits.

These limits are established by other teachings of the Church, and Catholic apologists need to be aware of them.

When it comes to the Kalaam argument, this is important because not all of the versions of it in circulation rely on assumptions consistent with Catholic teaching.

In particular, the foremost proponent of the Kalaam argument today—William Lane Craig—articulates it using concepts that clash with Catholic teaching, and Catholics who wish to use it need to be aware of this so that they can do the necessary filtering.

Specifically: Craig (who is not Catholic) holds that God is not eternal in the sense that the Church understands.

He does hold that God has always existed and that God would exist if the world (including time) had never come into being. However, he holds that due to the creation of the world, God exists inside of time rather than outside of it.

 

Eternity and Catholic Teaching

The classic definition of eternity was given by the Christian philosopher Boethius (c. 480-c. 525). He defined eternity this way:

Eternity, then, is the complete, simultaneous, and perfect possession of everlasting [Latin, interminabilis = “interminable,” “unending”] life; this will be clear from a comparison with creatures that exist in time (The Consolation of Philosophy, 5:6, emphasis added).

Eternity, then, is “the complete, simultaneous, and perfect possession of unending life.” It is something possessed by God and not possessed by creatures that exist in time. We may be everlasting—and we will be, for God will give us endless life—but God is fundamentally outside of time.

Boethius’s definition became standard in Catholic thought, and it was the definition in use when in 1215 the Fourth Lateran Council taught:

Firmly we believe and we confess simply that the true God is one alone, eternal, immense, and unchangeable, incomprehensible, omnipotent, and ineffable (DS 800).

The same definition was standard when in 1870 the First Vatican Council taught:

The Holy, Catholic, Apostolic and Roman Church believes and acknowledges that there is one true and living God, creator and lord of heaven and earth, almighty, eternal, immeasurable, incomprehensible, infinite in will, understanding and every perfection (Dei Filius, 1:1; DS 3001).

St. John Paul II made the implications of this more explicit when he taught:

These facts of revelation also express the rational conviction to which one comes when one considers that God is the subsisting Being, and therefore necessary, and therefore eternal.

Because he cannot not be, he cannot have beginning or end nor a succession of moments in the only and infinite act of his existence.

Right reason and revelation wonderfully converge on this point.

Being God, absolute fullness of being, (ipsum Esse subsistens), his eternity “inscribed in the terminology of being” must be understood as the “indivisible, perfect, and simultaneous possession of an unending life,” and therefore as the attribute of being absolutely “beyond time” (General Audience, Sept. 4, 1985).

Catholic teaching thus holds that God is eternal in the sense of being “absolutely beyond time” and that for him there is no “succession of moments in the only and infinite act of his existence.”

Everything God knows, he knows at once, and everything God does, he does at once. He doesn’t learn something, wait a little while, and then learn something new. Neither does he do something, wait a little while, and then do something new. His knowledge and his actions are all timeless and simultaneous.

 

Implications for Time

The fact that God is outside of time has implications for how we view time itself. Two key concepts we need to understand are called eternalism and presentism.

    • Eternalism is the view that the past, present, and future are all real from the ultimate perspective—that is, the perspective of God in eternity.
    • Presentism can be understood different ways, but here we will be concerned with what can be called “strict presentism,” which means that from the ultimate perspective, only the present is real. The past and the future do not exist at all.

If God is eternal, it is very difficult to see how presentism can be true. In fact, I would say that the ideas of divine eternity and strict presentism are mutually exclusive.

The reason is that, as John Paul II stated, there is no “succession of moments” for God. The “eternal now” in which God dwells constitutes “the only and infinite act of his existence.”

This means that everything that God does, he does simultaneously, and that includes creating all the different moments in time that we inhabit.

Thus, in his timeless, eternal now, God is simultaneously creating the stretch of time that we call 2021 . . . and the stretch of time we call 2022 . . . and 2023 . . . and so on.

But if God creates something, it is real from his perspective, and so 2021 is just as real to God as 2022 and 2023 and every other year in the history of the universe.

For God, our past, present, and future are equally real, and that implies eternalism.

 

Catholic Presentism?

There are Catholic thinkers who refer to themselves as presentists, but I am not aware of any who hold the strict presentism.

The response I’ve received when pointing out the fact that God must be eternally and simultaneously creating all the moments in history has been to the effect of:

Yes, of course, from God’s perspective, all of history must be real.

What I want to emphasize by speaking of presentism is that from our perspective in time the past is no longer real, and the future is not yet real. The passage of time is not an illusion.

And I agree with that. The passage of time is not an illusion. We are clearly moving through time, and if you take time as your frame of reference rather than eternity, the past and the future aren’t real, but the present is.

If these points are agreed to, whether one wants to call one’s position eternalism (viewing things from God’s eternal frame of reference) or presentism (viewing them from our temporal frame of reference) may be more a matter of semantics than substance.

But this Catholic presentism is not the same as the strict presentism described above, because that view holds that the past and the future are not just unreal from our perspective, but from God’s too. They simply don’t exist at all.

The eternalist (or Catholic presentist position we’ve described) has implications for the Kalaam argument. In particular, it has implications for two of the premises in Craig’s key arguments.

 

Actual Infinities

One of Craig’s key arguments goes like this:

1) An actually infinite number of things cannot exist.

2) A beginningless series of events in time entails an actually infinite number of things.

3) Therefore, a beginningless series of events in time cannot exist.

Here the problematic premise is the first.

The Christian faith holds that God will give us endless life in the future. We will not pass out of existence either at our death or at any point thereafter.

Viewed from within time, this endless existence is a potential infinite—meaning that we will experience an unlimited number of days, but those days don’t all exist at the same time.

However, from God’s perspective outside of time, they do all exist, because God is simultaneously creating each one of them, making them real from his perspective.

As a result, there are an actually infinite number of days from God’s perspective, and so actual infinities can exist in that frame of reference.

This means that the first premise of the argument is false from this perspective, and that fact undermines its conclusion.

On eternalism, the Christian faith implies that an actual infinity of future days does exist, and that implies that an actual infinity of past days can exist.

Speaking from our perspective inside time, this past infinity of days wouldn’t all exist at once—meaning they’re not an actual infinity from our perspective any more than the infinity of future days ahead of us is.

In fact, this corresponds to the view of Aristotle (who pioneered the concept of non-actual infinities). He held that the world had existed endlessly into the past, but this wasn’t a problem because all those days didn’t exist at the same time, making them a non-actual infinity.

 

Forming an Infinite by Successive Addition

Craig’s other key argument goes like this:

1) The series of events in time is a collection formed by adding one member after another.

2) A collection formed by adding one member after another cannot be actually infinite.

3) Therefore, the series of events in time cannot be actually infinite.

Here, again, the problematic premise is the first.

(Actually, the second premise also either involves a fallacy or is just false, but we’ll focus on the first one here.)

While it may be true that, from a perspective inside time, events grow in number by adding one new event after another, this isn’t true from God’s perspective.

On Christian eternalism, God exists in a single, timeless moment and does all of his creating activity simultaneously.

He thus is not creating the different years of history in a one-after-the-other fashion. He creates all of them at once, including the infinite years of life ahead of us. From the eternal perspective, Flash! An infinity of future years exists.

And so, the first premise would be false.

 

Craig’s Position

Craig appears sensitive to these considerations, and thus he is a strong advocate of strict presentism—to the point that he is willing to say that, since the creation of time, God has a temporal mode of existence.

I think this is something he would have to do, because if the present is the only thing that exist, it would force changes in God’s knowledge.

For example, at one moment, God would know “It is currently 12:00 p.m.,” but then a minute later he would know “It is currently 12:01 p.m.” This is because God knows whatever is true, and if only the present is real then what is true changes from moment to moment.

God’s knowledge thus would have to change to keep up with changing reality, and so God would be changeable rather than changeless, and thus subject to time.

The alternative would be to say that, from his perspective outside of time, God knows things like “At point X in time, it is 12:00 p.m. and at point Y in time, it is 12:01 p.m.” This allows God to know both facts about time simultaneously, in a changeless manner that preserves his eternity.

These two ways of looking at things are often framed in philosophical discussions in terms of the “A-theory of time” and the “B-theory of time.” Without getting into the weeds, the A-theory is associated with (but not the same thing as) presentism, while the B-theory is associated with eternalism.

Also important to the discussion is the distinction between “tensed propositions,” which change their truth value over time (e.g., “It is now 12:00 p.m.”) and “tenseless propositions,” which do not (e.g., “At point X in time, it is 12:00 p.m.”).

Tensed propositions are important for the A-theory (also called the “tensed theory of time”) and presentism, while a tenseless understanding is important for the B-theory (or “tenseless theory of time”) and eternalism.

If you read Craig’s works and watch his presentations, he frequently appeals to tensed propositions, the A-theory, and presentism in order to defend his philosophical arguments for the universe having a beginning.

They are key to his presentation. In fact, he has said that he thinks that the importance of the tensed theory of time for the Kalaam argument cannot be overstated.

He’s also acknowledged that if the B-theory of time or an atemporal understanding is true, it would damage to his presentations. He would abandon the argument from successive addition (as we noted should be done, above) and that he would have to reformulate defenses of other aspects of the argument, though the scientific evidence points to the universe having a beginning.

 

Implications for Catholic Apologists

In light of what we’ve seen, Catholic apologists need to be aware that they cannot simply take Craig’s presentations of the Kalaam argument and make them their own, repeating them as if they were all consistent with Catholic teaching.

Instead, they need to use critical thinking to sort the elements that are from the elements that aren’t.

In particular, they need to be aware that the Church disagrees with Craig when it comes to God having a temporal mode of existence and having knowledge that changes (as with tensed propositions and the A-theory of time).

For a Catholic, his arguments dealing with the A-theory and tensed propositions need serious revision or abandonment.

Similarly, if God creates all the moments of time simultaneously from the perspective of his eternal now, it has implications for the past and the future, as well as the present, being real.

This undermines the premises of the two key philosophical arguments Craig makes for a finite history (i.e., that actual infinities cannot exist and that the events in time are formed by successive addition from God’s perspective).

While Catholic teaching has serious implications for the kind of arguments that can be used in support of the overall Kalaam argument, and while careful discernment is needed on this point, I agree that the argument is still sound.

I disagree with Craig that the philosophical arguments for the universe having a beginning work, but I agree with him that the scientific evidence does point in this direction, and so I ultimately agree with him that a reformulated version of the argument can be used.

Can an Actual Infinity Exist?

We know that God created the universe a finite amount of time ago, but defenders of the Kalaam cosmological argument say that God had to do it this way. He had no other choice.

William Lane Craig has proposed the following argument to support this claim:

1) An actually infinite number of things cannot exist.

2) A beginningless series of events in time entails an actually infinite number of things.

3) Therefore, a beginningless series of events in time cannot exist.

Depending on your view of time, there are potential problems with the second premise—as I’ve written elsewhere.

However, here I’d like to consider the first premise.

Is it true that an actually infinite number of things can’t exist?

 

What’s an “Actual” Infinite?

We need to be aware of the difference between what philosophers and mathematicians call “potential” infinities and “actual” infinities.

    • Something is potentially infinite if it goes on endlessly, but there is no frame of reference in which all of its elements exist.
    • Something is actually infinite if it goes on endlessly and there is a frame of reference in which all its elements exist.

For example, suppose that you have a machine that makes cubes. Today it makes a cube, tomorrow it makes a cube, and it keeps on like that endlessly. No matter how many days you go into the future, there will still be a finite (limited) number of cubes.

From within the perspective of time, there is no day where the “infinity-eth” cube pops out of the machine, because “infinity” is not a number on the number line. There is no “number just before infinity,” and so you can’t count to infinity.

Yet the series of cubes that the machine will make is endless, which is what “infinite” means—unlimited or unending (Latin, in- “not” + finis = “limit, end”).

So, while the number of cubes you have grows toward infinity, it never gets there. That’s why the cubes would be said to be potentially infinite rather than actually infinite—because they don’t all exist at the same time.

But suppose you didn’t have a cube-making machine. Suppose instead that God decided to create an infinite number of cubes all at once. Bam! It’s done. All in a flash.

In this case, you would have an infinite number of cubes—that all exist at once—and so that would be an actually infinite set of cubes.

The key point to remember is that both potential infinites and actual infinites involve limitless numbers of things. The difference is that in a potential infinity these elements don’t all exist at once, while in an actual infinity, they do.

 

Can Actual Infinities Exist?

While many authors assert that actual infinities can’t exist, we should test this. Can we think of anything actually infinite?

How about numbers?

We often represent the set of natural numbers like this: {0, 1, 2, 3 . . . }. The reason we put the ellipsis (the three dots) at the end is to say that this series of numbers goes on forever in the same way it began, with one number after another, with no end to them.

That’s an infinite set!

And all those numbers already exist. It’s not like there’s a mathematician somewhere inventing new numbers in his workshop.

We may make up names for new numbers—like the number googol, which is 10-to-the-power-of-100, or googolplex, which is 10-to-the-power-of-googol—but we didn’t create these numbers. We only named them.

Even before they were thought of or named, it would remain true that googol multiplied by 2 is 2 googol, that googol minus google is 0, and that googol divided by google is 1.

So, it appears that an infinite quantity of natural numbers exists, whether we’ve thought of or named them or not.

Since the set of numbers does not grow with time—only our knowledge of them does—the set of natural numbers is an actually infinite set, as mathematicians commonly acknowledge.

 

The Truth of the Matter

Numbers are not the only actual infinity we can think of. There also are truths (facts), as we can easily see:

    • It is true that 1 + 1 = 2.
    • It is true that 2 + 1 = 3.
    • It is true that 3 + 1 = 4.
    • And so on.

So, not only does an actually infinite quantity of numbers exist, an actually infinite quantity of truths also does.

How might a defender of the Kalaam argument respond to this?

 

The Nature of Numbers and Truths

It’s easy to point out that there is a difference between numbers and truths and the kind of objects we see in the world around us.

For example, if I have two cubes that I’m holding in my hands, I’m physically touching them. But I don’t seem to be touching the number 2. Numbers aren’t physical objects you can see, hear, or touch.

Neither are truths. It may be a truth that Abraham Lincoln died in 1865, but I can’t hold this truth in my hands like an apple or put a ruler beside it and measure how long it is.

Things like numbers and truths seem to be in a different category than things like cubes and apples. Things in the first category are often called abstract objects, while those in the latter are often called concrete objects. We also might call them physical objects.

The sciences have given us a lot of information about how physical objects work, but we can’t use science to investigate abstract ones. They lie in the realm of philosophy, and among philosophers there are different views about their nature.

Some philosophers (known as anti-realists) deny that abstract objects are real and propose other ways of understanding them. Other philosophers (known as realists) hold that they do exist, but again there are different understandings (e.g., do abstract objects exist in an abstract realm of some kind? do they only exist in physical objects? are they based in the mind of God?).

 

Options for the Kalaam Defender

A Kalaam defender could adopt an anti-realist position and say that things like numbers and truths simply do not exist, which would mean that there aren’t actual infinities of these—because numbers and truths don’t exist in the first place!

But this seems hard for many to imagine, including various supporters of the Kalaam argument.

There is another option, which is to draw a line between the two classes of objects and say something like, “Look, whether or not actual infinities of abstract objects exist (maybe they do; maybe they don’t), that’s not what I’m talking about. When I say that actual infinities can’t exist, I mean that they can’t exist concretely, in the physical world.”

A person taking this position could acknowledge that actual infinities of abstract objects can exist. What he disputes is that actual infinities of concrete, physical ones can.

 

Why Not?

The question would be: Why not? Why can’t actual infinities of physical objects be real?

This question is particularly acute from a Christian perspective, since the Christian faith holds that God exists and that he is omnipotent, which means that he can create anything that does not involve a logical contradiction.

So, let’s do a thought experiment:

Imagine a cubic foot of empty space that has a single hydrogen atom in it. If we can imagine that, so can God.

Now imagine a second cubic foot of empty space sitting right next to it, also with a hydrogen atom in it. God can imagine that, too.

Now put a third cubic foot of space next to that, also with a hydrogen atom, so that we have a row of three.

Then imagine a fourth, a fifth, a sixth, and so on. God can imagine each of these as the line of cubic feet extends off into the distance.

In fact—due to his omniscience—God can imagine any number of such units. Unless there is a logical contradiction involved, God could imagine a cubic foot of space with a hydrogen atom for every natural number.

And so, God can imagine an actually infinite volume of space, with a single hydrogen atom in each cubic foot.

Either this scenario involves a logical contradiction or it doesn’t. If it doesn’t, then God can imagine it, since God can do anything logically possible.

And it does not appear to involve a contradiction. As even many defenders of the Kalaam argument admit, the mathematics of infinity are consistent and do not contain logical contradictions.

This situation isn’t like saying, “Suppose God imagines a four-sided triangle.” Not even God can visualize that, because “four-sided triangle” is a contradiction in terms.

“Four-sided” and “triangular” mean different and contradictory things. This expression is just word salad—not something that is actually meaningful.

But our volume of space isn’t like that. Even our puny minds can imagine a row of cubic feet with hydrogen atoms in them. God’s mind is infinite, and so he can imagine the line of cubic feet extending on endlessly—and there doesn’t seem to be a logical contradiction involved in him doing that.

If there’s not, then we’re ready to add a new element to our thought experiment.

 

“Let There Be Space!”

Because of his omnipotence, God can do anything that doesn’t involve a logical contradiction. So, if God can imagine something, he can also create it.

As a result, if the idea of an infinite row of cubic feet of space—each with a hydrogen atom—doesn’t involve a logical contradiction, then God can make it real.

God thus could create an infinite number of hydrogen atoms and an infinite volume of space to contain them.

If God chooses, actual infinities of physical things could exist!

The only way to avoid this would be to say that, even though the idea of finite space with finite atoms is logically coherent, a contradiction in terms is generated if we extend this to infinity.

In that case, God couldn’t imagine or create this any more than he could a four-sided triangle.

But in that case, I want to know: What’s the contradiction?

As we’ve discussed, a Christian who understands God’s omnipotence should affirm that God can make something unless it is shown to involve a logical contradiction.

The Kalaam defender thus needs to name the contradiction: Which are the specific terms that contradict?

And it won’t do to change the scenario and pose some other one where a new logically contradictory entity is subtly introduced. That happens all too often.

Changing the scenario is what you do when you can’t deal with the current one.

Neither is it sufficient to say, “Hey, infinities have weird properties.” Yes, they do. That doesn’t mean they’re beyond the reach of God’s omnipotence.

So please, deal with the thought experiment I’ve described, flesh out its terms in detail, and name which terms contradict each other—just like how I pointed out that “four-sided” and “triangular” contradict.

Either that or be prepared to acknowledge that God has the power to create actual infinities of physical objects.

 

Grim Reapers, Paradoxes, and Infinite History

We know from Scripture that God created the world a finite amount of time ago, but was that the only option he had? Could God have created a world with an infinite history?

Defenders of the Kalaam cosmological argument claim that he couldn’t have done so.

To show that, they would need to demonstrate that the idea of an infinite history involves a logical contradiction.

Some recent attempts to do this involve paradoxes that have been proposed by different authors.

Let’s look at a couple and see what we can learn.

 

The (Squished) Grim Reaper Paradox

The core of what has become known as the Grim Reaper paradox was proposed by Jose Bernardete, and the argument has taken different forms.

Here I’ll present a version that is close to the original. I’ll refer to it as the “squished” version for reasons that will become obvious.

Suppose that a guy named Fred is alive at 12:00 noon.

However, there are an infinite number of grim reapers waiting to kill him. For the sake of convenience, we will give the reapers names based on the negative numbers, with the last reaper being Reaper 0.

If Fred is still alive at 1 p.m., Reaper 0 will encounter him and kill him. However, before that, Reaper -1 will encounter Fred at 12:30 p.m. and kill him. Even before that, Reaper -2 will encounter Fred at 12:15 p.m. and kill him. But Reaper -3 will encounter him at 12:07:30 p.m., and so on, with each reaper set to encounter (and kill) Fred in half the remaining distance back to noon.

Which reaper will kill Fred?

The way the situation has been set up, we have a paradox. Reaper 0 should not kill Fred, because Fred should already have been killed by Reaper -1. But this reaper shouldn’t kill him either, because he should have been killed by Reaper -2. And Reaper -3 should have killed him before that, and so on.

It thus looks like Fred can’t possibly survive past 12:00 noon, but it’s impossible to name which reaper kills him. Paradox.

I called the above version “squished” because it squishes the infinite series of grim reapers into a single hour. But we don’t have to do it that way. We’ll see another version later.

 

The Problem with the Paradox

The resolution of this paradox is fairly straightforward. It has envisioned a situation where Fred begins alive and then will be killed by the first grim reaper he encounters.

The problem is that—if the series of grim reapers is infinite—then it must have no beginning.

To suppose that an infinite series of whole numbers has both a first and last member involves what I’ve called the First-and-Last Fallacy.

    • Infinite series can have no beginning ( . . . -3, -2, -1, 0)
    • They can have no end (0, 1, 2, 3 . . .)
    • Or they can lack both a beginning and an end ( . . . -3, -2, -1, 0, 1, 2, 3 . . . )

But if a series has both a beginning and an end, then it’s finite.

The series of reapers set to kill Fred has an end—Reaper 0—but if that’s the case, it cannot have a beginning.

This means that there is no first grim reaper that Fred encounters, just as there is no “first negative number.”

The idea of a first negative number involves a logical contradiction, and therefore the (Squished) Grim Reaper paradox is proposing a situation that cannot exist.

 

The (Spread-Out) Grim Reaper Paradox

To make the Grim Reaper Paradox more relevant to the Kalaam argument, some have proposed a new version that spreads out the grim reapers over an infinite history rather than squishing them into a single hour.

We can put the spread-out version like this:

Suppose that Fred has always been alive, all the way through an infinite past.

Suppose that there is an infinite series of grim reapers set to kill Fred, and they are set to kill him in sequence on New Year’s Day.

On New Year’s Day this year, Reaper 0 is set to kill him if he is still alive. But on New Year’s Day last year, Reaper -1 was set to kill him, and Reaper -2 the year before that, and so on.

Which reaper kills Fred?

Exactly the same paradox results. Each reaper should not be able to kill Fred because a previous reaper should already have done the dirty work.

But the problem is the same: The situation is set up so that the only reaper that could kill Fred is the first one in a beginningless series, and a beginningless series has no first element.

The spread-out version of the paradox thus has the same flaw that the original did: It proposes an entity that involves a logical contradiction and so can’t exist.

 

Application to the Kalaam Argument

Kalaam defenders use paradoxes like this in an attempt to undermine the idea of an infinite history.

For example, on the rhetorical level, the strategy can work like this:

    • They encourage their audience to imagine a set of circumstances that could exist and that don’t involve a logical contradiction (e.g., Fred exists, a grim reaper is scheduled to kill him at some time).
    • They multiply the circumstance extending finitely into the past (suppose there are some other grim reapers who were also set to kill him previously).
    • They extend this infinitely into the past, generating a contradiction.
    • They point out this contradiction.
    • Finally, they assert that, since the infinite extension into the past caused the contradiction, we must reject the idea of an infinite past.

This reasoning is mistaken, because it isn’t the infinite history that’s the problem. It’s the fact that you’ve proposed a first element in a beginningless series.

Consider the following scenario:

    • Suppose that some guy named Fred exists.
    • Suppose that he existed last year.
    • And the year before that.
    • And that he’s always existed, with no beginning.

That involves an infinite history, but it doesn’t have a contradiction in it—because it does not propose a first element in a beginningless series.

It’s only when you introduce the latter that a contradiction occurs. So, it isn’t the infinite history that’s the problem but the impossible first element. Grim Reaper-like paradoxes thus are disguised forms of the First-and-Last Fallacy.

 

World Without End

Another way of seeing why the strategy used by Kalaam defenders is problematic is by flipping the arrow of time and considering a mirror image of the paradox that deals with the future:

Suppose that Fred is alive today and will remain alive as long as a grim reaper doesn’t kill him.

Suppose that there is an infinite series of grim reapers to kill him in the future and who we will name using the positive numbers, beginning with 0. Reaper 0 encounters Fred today, Reaper 1 encounters him tomorrow, Reaper 2 the day after, and so on.

But the reapers have agreed that the honor of killing Fred will go to the reaper with the highest number.

Which reaper kills Fred?

The way this scenario has been set up, the only reaper that can kill Fred is the last reaper.

But there can be no last reaper in a series that has no end, just as there can be no first reaper in a series that has no beginning.

The Future Reaper Paradox proposes the same kind of logically contradictory entity that the original paradoxes did.

And the problem is not the fact that the future is infinite in the scenario. The infinite future itself does not involve a contradiction, because it does not propose there being a last element in the series of days stretching into the future.

Indeed! From a Christian point of view, an infinite future is exactly what awaits us. The Christian faith teaches that God will give us endless life and there will be no day on which we pass out of existence. As a result, an orthodox Christian is committed to the idea of an infinite future.

It’s not the endlessness of the future that’s a problem in the above scenario, but the idea of that future containing a logically contradictory entity like the last member of an endless series of reapers.

In the same way, the idea of an infinite past is not a logical contradiction but the idea of a first reaper in a beginningless series.

 

The Underlying Assumptions

The paradoxes recently proposed in support of the Kalaam argument (and there are many) share a common set of assumptions:

    1. Suppose some past scenario (P) that involves a first member.
    2. Suppose some past scenario (P’) that does not have a first member.
    3. Suppose that P and P’ are the same scenario.

By contrast, corresponding future-oriented paradoxes have these assumptions:

    1. Suppose some future scenario (F) that involves a last member.
    2. Suppose some future scenario (F’) that does not have a last member.
    3. Suppose that F and F’ are the same scenario.

The way the paradoxes are fleshed out and expressed varies, and this can disguise the fact, but they all share the same set of assumptions.

As a result, they set up logical contradictions, but this does not tell us which of the premises must be rejected to diffuse the contradiction.

This is true of any such paradox. Consider the following geometrical one:

    1. Suppose there is some closed geometrical shape (S) that has three sides.
    2. Suppose that there is some closed geometrical shape (S’) that has four sides.
    3. Suppose that S and S’ are the same shape.

This scenario sets up the idea of a four-sided triangle, which is logically impossible. But in resolving the paradox, we don’t have to reject any particular premise.

We could reject the idea that S (the three-sided shape) exists; we could reject the idea that (S’) the four-sided shape exists; or we could reject the idea that S and S’ are the same and then conclude that there must be two shapes. Each of these is a legitimate option.

As a result, when considering past- or future-oriented paradoxes, we don’t have to reject the idea of an infinite past or an infinite future, because neither of these concepts generates a logical contradiction on its own.

It is only when we introduce a logically contradictory entity into these scenarios—like the first member of a beginningless series or the last member in an endless series—that a paradox results.

Those are the entities that need to be rejected, and the recently proposed paradoxes do not disprove either the idea of an infinite past or an infinite future.

Omnipotence and Infinite History

God chose to create the world a finite amount of time ago, but could he have chosen otherwise?

According to defenders of the Kalaam cosmological argument, the answer is no. He could not have done so, and the world must have a finite history. Even God could not create an infinite one.

Others, such as St. Thomas Aquinas, disagree and hold that God could have done this if he chose.

How can we navigate this issue?

The Burden of Proof

People who disagree sometimes get into squabbles about who has the burden of proof—that is, who needs to provide proof of their position.

While special rules may apply in a courtroom or in a formal debate, the answer for ordinary purposes is clear. It can be stated in the form of a simple and powerful rule.

The Iron Rule of the Burden of Proof: Whoever wants someone to change his mind has the burden of proof.

If I want you to change your mind, I need to give you evidence (arguments, proof) why you should do so. If you want me to change my mind, you need to.

Much needless squabbling would be avoided if people kept this rule in mind.

Applying this to our question:

    • If a Kalaam proponent wants to convince someone that God couldn’t create a world with an infinite history, he needs to provide evidence why he couldn’t.
    • If a Kalaam skeptic wants to convince someone that God could create a world with an infinite history, he needs to provide evidence why he could.
    • If they both want to convince each other, they both need to do this.

I’m a Kalaam skeptic, so let me give you the evidence that causes me to take this position.

“With God All Things Are Possible”

The Christian faith holds that God is all-powerful, or omnipotent. Jesus himself tells us, “With God all things are possible” (Matt. 19:26).

Thus, the default answer for any question that takes the form “Could God create X?” is “Yes.”

If you want to move off that default answer, you’ll need to show something very specific. This is because, over the centuries, theologians have discerned that there is only one type of situation that falls outside the scope of God’s omnipotence: logical contradictions.

No, God can’t make married bachelors, square circles, or four-sided triangles. Each of these involves a contradiction in terms, or what philosophers call a logical contradiction.

They don’t represent possible entities. They’re just word salad. They may at first sound like something that could exist, but as soon as you think about the meaning of the words involved, you realize that they can’t.

So, while “with God all things are possible,” these aren’t things. “Square circle” and “four-sided triangle” are just nonsense phrases.

“Infinite History”?

In light of this principle, if I ask myself, “Could God create a world with an infinite history?” my default answer will be “Yes”—just as it would be on any other subject.

For me to move off that default answer, I’d need to be shown that the concept of a world with an infinite history involves a logical contradiction.

The same should be true of every Christian who understands God’s omnipotence.

Thus far, despite extensive research, I have not been able to find a logical contradiction. And, as a result, I am of the opinion that one does not exist.

Consider Craig

Consider the arguments proposed by William Lane Craig, the best-known defender of the Kalaam argument.

He has spent an enormous amount of time thinking, writing, and defending it. If anyone should have found a logical contradiction in the concept, it should be him!

Yet, in his books, debates, speeches, and videos, I haven’t found him asserting that the concept of an infinite history involves a logical contradiction. If anything, he seems to carefully avoid saying that.

He concedes that the mathematics of infinity are logically consistent—that they don’t involve a logical contradiction—so, it isn’t that the concept of infinity is problematic.

Instead, he asserts that actual infinities can’t exist in the real world, so the real world’s history can’t be infinite.

But what is it about the concept of “infinity” and the concept of “history” that prevents the two from being brought together? Both concepts are fine on their own. Where’s the logical contradiction?

Craig never seems to say. Instead, I find him saying two things:

    1. An actual infinity that exists in the real world would be “metaphysically impossible.”
    2. If an actual infinity existed in the real world, the results would be “absurd.”

“Metaphysically Impossible”

Sometimes Craig states that it would be metaphysically impossible for the world to have an infinite history. What does this mean?

Philosophers and theologians speak about different types of possibility. For example:

    • Something is logically possible if it does not involve a contradiction in terms.
    • Something is metaphysically possible if it could happen in reality, even if the world operated under very different physical laws.
    • Something is physically possible if it could happen in our world, given the way its physical laws operate (e.g., the speed of light, conservation of mass and energy).
    • Something is practically possible if we could realistically do it, given our limitations (e.g., how much time we have, how big our budget is).

Philosophers often say that metaphysical possibility is notoriously hard to define, and from a secular perspective, this might be true.

However, for a Christian who understands God’s omnipotence, it shouldn’t be.

    1. God can do anything that doesn’t involve a logical contradiction.
    2. Therefore, God can make any world that doesn’t involve a logical contradiction.
    3. Therefore, anything that is logically possible is metaphysically possible.

For the Christian, logical possibility and metaphysical possibility are really two ways of describing the same thing.

If—on the logical level—there’s a contradiction in terms, then that means—on the metaphysical level—that there is a contradiction in the nature of the things those terms describe.

Let’s suppose that you want to draw a four-sided triangle. On the logical level, there is a contradiction between four-sidedness and being a triangle, and on the metaphysical level, triangular objects are such that they cannot have four sides.

As a result, the question of metaphysical impossibility collapses into the question of logical possibility.

Consequently, logical impossibility is what Craig needs to show if he wants to deny that God can’t make a world with an infinite history.

To say that such a thing would be metaphysically impossible is, for the Christian who understands God’s omnipotence, just another way of saying that it involves a logical contradiction.

“Absurd”

What about Craig’s other claim—that an actual infinity in the real world would result in “absurd” situations?

Craig makes this charge in connection with a famous thought experiment known as Hilbert’s Hotel, which was proposed by the mathematician David Hilbert.

It involves a hotel that has an infinite number of rooms, and—because of the strange properties that infinity has—you can imagine some very strange things happening at the hotel. (You can read about them at the link.)

There are various ways of responding. Hilbert’s Hotel actually isn’t as strange as it sounds once you think about what “infinite” means. Also, it’s just a physicalization of the concept of infinity, with one room for every natural number. So, if the idea of an infinite set of natural numbers doesn’t involve a logical contradiction, neither should a physical representation of it.

However, to keep our discussion concise, I want to focus on this: “Absurd” does not mean “logically contradictory.”

Something is absurd if it strikes us as surprising, counter-intuitive, and contrary to our expectations—prompting us to have an impulse to reject the idea out of hand.

But it turns out that the world contains many things that strike us as absurd and yet turn out to be true. This is the case regardless of one’s persuasions. One can be Christian, Jewish, Muslim, Atheist, or anything else, and the world still contains a lot of strange, “absurd” things.

Lots of people—in history and today—have found each of the following claims absurd:

    • An infinitely loving God would allow innocent people and animals to suffer.
    • God would send someone to hell.
    • God became man.
    • God died on a cross.
    • There is one God, who is a Trinity of Persons.
    • Transubstantiation occurs.
    • God created the world out of nothing.
    • The earth is a sphere.
    • The sun does not orbit the earth.
    • Man can build machines that will enable him to fly.
    • Man can go to the moon.
    • Modern life forms are the product of a process of evolution stretching back billions of years.
    • There was a beginning to time.
    • Space and time are not absolutes but can be warped by gravity.
    • When you move faster, time slows down.
    • Heavier objects do not fall appreciably faster than lighter ones.
    • Atoms exist.
    • In the Monty Hall Problem, the best strategy is to switch your bet after the first door is opened.

Yet each of these is true. So, from a Christian perspective, we can say that God has created a world where a lot of “absurd” things in it.

Consequently, if we want our beliefs to be accurate, we need to be willing to consider ideas that strike us as absurd and not simply dismiss them on this basis.

The fact that something seems absurd is not a reliable guide to what God can do, and so it’s not enough to allow us to say, “God can’t do that.”

If we want to say that God can’t make a world with an infinite history, we need more than gesturing at a situation and saying it’s absurd.

We need to know what logical contradiction it involves. We need to be able to name the terms that produce a logical contradiction.

So far, Craig hasn’t identified one, but that’s what we need to see.

Until he or someone else can show that the idea of infinite history involves a contradiction in terms (and name the terms that conflict!), any Christian who understands God’s omnipotence should remain with the default position that this would be within God’s power.

Using the Kalaam Argument Correctly

In recent years, one of the most popular arguments for the existence of God has been the Kalaam cosmological argument.

Ultimately, I think this argument is successful, but many of the ways it has been employed are unsuccessful.

It is an argument that needs to be used carefully—with the proper qualifiers.

 

Stating the Argument

We can state the Kalaam argument like this:

1) Everything that has a beginning has a cause.

2) The universe has a beginning.

3) Therefore, the universe has a cause (which would be God).

Is this argument valid? Is it sound?

Valid arguments are ones that use a correct logical form—regardless of whether their premises are true. The Kalaam argument falls into this category, which is not disputed by its critics.

If a valid argument has true premises, then its conclusion also will be true. Valid arguments that have true premises are called sound arguments, and I agree that the argument’s premises are true:

1) It is true that whatever has a beginning has a cause.

2) And it is true that the universe has a beginning (approximately 13.8 billion years ago, according to Big Bang cosmology).

Since the Kalaam argument is valid and has true premises, it is a sound argument.

 

Using the Argument Apologetically

The Kalaam argument is sound from the perspective of logic, but how useful is it from the perspective of apologetics? There are many arguments that are sound, but sometimes they are not very useful in practice.

For example, in their famous book Principia Mathematica, Bertrand Russell and Alfred North Whitehead spend the first 360 pages of the book covering basic principles that build up to them rigorously proving that 1 + 1 = 2.

While their book is of interest to mathematicians, and their proof extremely well thought-out, it is so complex that it is not of practical use for a popular audience. For ordinary people, there are much simpler ways to prove that 1 + 1 = 2. (If needed, just put one apple on a table, put another one next to it, and count the apples both individually and together.)

Complexity is not the only thing that can limit an argument’s usefulness. Another is the willingness of people to grant the truth of its premises. Here is where some of the limitations of the Kalaam argument appear. While it is very simple to state and understand, defending the premises is more involved.

 

The First Premise

The first premise—that everything that has a beginning has a cause—is intuitive and is accepted by most people.

Some object to this premise on philosophical grounds or on scientific ones, such as by pointing to the randomness of quantum physics.

Both the philosophical and the scientific arguments can get technical quickly, but a skilled apologist—at least one who is actually familiar with quantum mechanics (!)—would still be able to navigate such objections without getting too far over the heads of a popular audience.

This—plus the fact that a popular audience’s sympathies will be with the first premise—mean that the argument retains its usefulness with a general audience.

 

The Second Premise

The second premise—that the universe had a beginning—is also widely accepted today, due in large part to Big Bang cosmology. A popular audience will thus be generally sympathetic to the second premise.

That’s apologetically useful, but we need to look more closely at how the second premise can be supported when challenged.

Since “The Bible says the universe has a beginning” will not be convincing to those who are not already believers, there are two approaches to doing this—the scientific and the philosophical.

 

The Scientific Approach

For an apologist, the approach here is straight forward: For a popular level audience, simply present a popular-level account of the evidence that has led cosmologists to conclude that the Big Bang occurred.

On this front, the principal danger for the apologist is overselling the evidence in one of several ways.

First, many apologists do not keep up with developments in cosmology, and they may be relying on an outdated account of the Big Bang.

For example, about 40 years ago, it was common to hear cosmologists speak of the Big Bang as an event that involved a singularity—where all matter was compressed into a point of infinite density and when space and time suddenly sprang into existence.

That view is no longer standard in cosmology, and today no apologist should be speaking as if this is what the science shows. Apologists need to be familiar with the current state of cosmological thought (as well as common misunderstandings of the Big Bang) and avoid misrepresenting current cosmological views.

Thus, they should not say that the Big Bang is proof that the universe had an absolute beginning. While the Big Bang is consistent with an absolute beginning, cosmologists have not been able to rule out options like there being a prior universe.

One way apologists have dealt with this concern is to point to the Borde-Guth-Vilenkin (BGV) theorem, which seeks to show that—on certain assumptions—even if there were one or more prior universes, there can’t be an unlimited number of them.

It’s fair to point to this theorem, but it would be a mistake for an apologist to present it as final proof, because the theorem depends on certain assumptions (e.g., that the universe has—on average—been expanding throughout its history) that cannot be taken for granted.

Further, apologists should be aware that authors of the theorem—Alan Guth and Alexander Vilenkin—do not agree that it shows the universe had to have a beginning. Guth apparently believes that the universe does not have a beginning, and Vilenkin states that all the theorem shows is that the expansion of the universe had to have a beginning, not the universe itself.

It thus would misrepresent the BGV theorem as showing that the scientific community has concluded that the universe had to have a beginning, even if it were before the Big Bang. (It also would be apologetically dangerous and foolish to do so, as the facts I’ve just mentioned could be thrown in the apologist’s face, discrediting him before his audience.)

Most fundamentally, the findings of science are always provisional, and the history of science contains innumerable cases where scientific opinion as reversed as new evidence has been found.

Consequently, apologists should never sell Big Bang cosmology—or any other aspect of science—as final “proof.”

This does not mean that apologists can’t appeal to scientific evidence. When the findings of science point in the direction aspects of the Faith, it is entirely fair to point that out. They just must not be oversold.

 

The Philosophical Approach

Prior to the mid-20th century, Big Bang cosmology had not been developed, and the scientific approach to defending the Kalaam argument’s second premise was not available.

Consequently, earlier discussions relied on philosophical arguments to try to show that the universe must have a beginning.

Such arguments remain a major part of the discussion today, and new philosophical ways of defending the second premise have been proposed.

Authors have different opinions about how well these work, but in studying them, I find myself agreeing with St. Thomas Aquinas that they do not. Thus far, I have not discovered any philosophical argument—ancient or modern—that I thought proved its case.

This is not to say that they don’t have superficial appeal. They do; otherwise, people wouldn’t propose them.

But when one thinks them through carefully, they all contain hidden flaws that keep them from succeeding—some of which are being discussed in this series.

I thus do not rely on philosophical arguments in my own presentation of the Kalaam argument.

 

Conclusion

The Kalaam cosmological argument is a valid and sound argument. It does prove that the universe has a cause, which can meaningfully be called God.

As a result, it can be used by apologists, and its simplicity makes it particularly attractive.

I use it myself, such as in my short, popular-level book The Words of Eternal Life.

However, the argument needs to be presented carefully. The scientific evidence we currently have is consistent with and suggestive of the world having a beginning in the finite past, though this evidence must not be oversold.

The philosophical arguments for the universe having a beginning are much more problematic. I do not believe that the ones developed to date work, and so I do not use them.

I thus advise other apologists to think carefully before doing so and to rigorously test these arguments: Seek out counterarguments, carefully consider them, and see if you can show why the arguments don’t work.

It is not enough that we find an argument convenient or initially plausible. We owe it to the truth, and honesty in doing apologetics compels us not to use arguments just because we want them to be true.